Yesterday at the
NYU Tax Policy Colloquium, Jim Hines and Kyle Logue presented their paper, “DelegatingTax.” The paper’s main arguments are: (1)
Congress does less delegation of lawmaking authority in tax than in other areas
of law, such as environmental regulation, (2) the grounds for favoring
significant delegation in other areas also apply to tax, and therefore (3) it
might be desirable for Congress to increase the degree to which it delegates lawmaking
authority in the tax area.
Possible examples
of greater delegation that the paper discusses include (a) giving the Fed
authority to make tax rate changes for countercyclical reasons, (b) giving greater
discretion, with regard to the design of tax preferences either to the Treasury
or to subject-matter experts, and (c) empowering a commission, a la the
military base-closing commission of some years back, with the authority to make
broad determinations with regard to which tax preferences might be eliminated
to fund either lower rates (in a 1986-style reform) or else long-term deficit
reduction.
This was an
interesting paper and I am generally sympathetic to its line of argument. To be sure, it is hard to pin down what
exactly one means by greater versus lesser delegation (although there clearly
is some underlying content there).
Moreover, if it could be defined crisply enough, one might want to try to
examine empirically the relative delegation in tax versus other areas in the
U.S., and as between the U.S. and other countries.
Further thoughts
that I had upon reading the paper are contained in the following, which is an
expanded and reorganized version of notes that I prepared for myself in order
to be ready for the session:
1) What do we mean by delegation of tax
lawmaking authority, and where do we tend to find it?
(a) It has
something to do with the choice between rules and standards, where the latter
might be viewed as involving greater delegation, but is not exactly the same
thing. (E.g., one could delegate either
more or less under either a rules-based or a standards-based approach.)
(b) If we are
talking about tax delegation, we should keep in mind delegation to the courts,
not just to the Treasury Department.
Most judicial decisions on tax in the U.S. involve statutory
interpretation, and thus not only could be overturned by Congress ex post, but
in many cases could have been headed off ex ante if Congress had wanted to
specify more precisely what it meant.
(Often it doesn’t, however – apparently preferring to delegate.)
(c) Congress appears
highly inclined to delegate in cases where it is applying very broad legal
concepts that have murky or unclear underlying economic content. Examples include:
(i) Section 482, which
authorizes the Treasury to reallocate taxable income between related parties based
on the principles of clear reflection of income and preventing evasion. Under the regulations, this is generally done
under an “arm’s length” standard. One
asks the counterfactual question: “What would the related parties have done if
acting at arm’s length?” and tries as best as one can to finesse the problem
that this question commonly lacks a coherent, much less discernible, answer. My point here is not that doing this is a bad
idea (not doing it would probably be even worse), but that the difficulty of
devising workable principles has apparently induced Congress to punt /
delegate.
(ii) Debt versus equity –
This is the re-delegation that failed. As is well-known, there is no coherent basis
on which the tax law can distinguish debt from equity, at least in close or
mixed cases, and there also is no particular policy reason for treating them so
distinctively. Congress for decades
delegated the whole issue to the courts. However, in 1969, it passed Code section 385, instructing the Treasury
to issue regulations sorting out the mess.
The Treasury tried for a while, issuing two sets of proposed regulations
(if I recall correctly) that it then decided not to finalize. So delegating / punting the issue to the courts
remained the prevailing norm.
(iii) Economic substance requirement
– Case law has long held that tax-motivated transactions will be ineffective if
they lack requisite economic substance and/or business purpose. This is of course a “standard” developed by
the courts and for decades left alone by Congress. When Congress finally codified the economic
substance approach, for use in applying penalties, it bent over backwards to
make clear that it was not adjusting or revising the prior common law approach
in any way, apart from one distinct matter: it provided that taxpayers must meet
both the “objective” and “subjective” aspects of the prevailing test, whereas
case law had been divided as to whether one needed to satisfy both, or just
either one.
2) Is there less tax delegation, and if
so why?
(a) Presumably, Congress
will only delegate lawmaking authority (or delegate “more” rather than “less”
when it realistically has the choice) where the relevant decision-makers
conclude that the political benefits of doing so exceed the political costs.
Making a
consequential political decision often has both political benefits and costs. One gets the credit but also the blame; one
pleases the winners but also angers the losers.
Given, however, that politicians both often like to exercise power and
benefit from doing so (e.g., reputationally and in fundraising), presumably “extra”
delegation that was not practically necessary tends to reflect some particular
motivation.
Here are 3
representative examples:
(i) Public interest reasons
for delegating: If, say, an independent agency can actually do a demonstrably
better job than Congress, and members of Congress believe that on the whole this
will be to their political benefit, they may delegate for entirely “good”
reasons. A classic example is delegation
of power over monetary policy to the Fed.
(Admittedly, this example risks becoming obsolete in the era of Rand
Paul. I suspect that, if were necessary
to pass new legislation retaining the Fed’s current authority over monetary policy,
it would fail in the House and be filibustered in the Senate.)
(ii) Symbolic politics:
Here an example is the creation of the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA). To be clear, I certainly agree that the creation
of the EPA was important substantive policymaking, with real effects that I believe
were on the whole decidedly good. But to legislators at the time, I would think
that it had an important symbolic element: By creating a new agency, one takes
the credit for “doing something” about environmental concerns. But since the EPA is the party actually making
decisions that involve tough tradeoffs (or winners versus losers), it gets the
blame on the implementation end.
(iii) Prisoner’s dilemma: Suppose
there is broad consensus that we all lose overall from an array of parochial
benefits. But no one wants to give up
his or her narrow benefit, unless enough others are doing the same. Congress’s creation of a military
base-closing commission (with Congress to vote the final recommendations up or
down, with no amendments permitted) is a classic example.
(b) In practice,
agreement to delegation appears to require broad underlying consensus regarding the general
policy approach that Congress However,
while broad delegation’s reliance on the existence of underlying consensus appears
clear empirically (at least based on casual observation), it is less clear why,
as a theoretical matter, this should be so.
One could, for example, imagine political players who strenuously
disagree but are mutually uncertain of success handing things over to an
arbiter. But my impression is that this
doesn’t generally happen.
(c) The conditions
for broad delegation are generally missing in current tax politics. Politicians appear not to view the political
benefit as exceeding the political cost, and an important reason is the lack of
underlying consensus. With respect to
particular examples:
(i) The Fed and tax rates
– Even when there was greater consensus than we have today regarding
countercyclical fiscal and monetary policy, why would Congress hand over tax
rate authority to the Fed? Isn’t it more
fun to get the credit oneself for cutting taxes during recessions? And while Congress could reasonably have
anticipated that it would be less eager to clamp down when there was inflation
risk, at least the Fed was still there as a backstop via monetary policy.
(ii) Design of tax preferences
– Here is where one could most readily imagine it happening. Indeed, there are a couple of small areas in
the law (e.g., with regard to low-income housing credits and state agencies)
where delegation has indeed expanded a bit.
(iii) Repealing tax
preferences to fund a rate cut or reduce the fiscal gap – This would be
just like military base-closing if there were sufficient underlying consensus,
along with willingness to lose one’s own favored items so long as others shared
in the haircut. But there simply is no
such underlying consensus. What is more, many of the underlying items are just
too big for their proponents to be philosophical about losing them even if lots
of other stuff is nicked as well.
3) Would more tax delegation be
beneficial?
(a) Analogy
between delegation to an independent agency and the existence of nonprofit
firms – There is a rich law and economics literature concerning when
and where we observe the use of nonprofit firms – for example, in charity work,
higher education, and the fine arts. The
dominant account, for example from Henry Hansmann’s work, emphasizes that it is
a response to the concern (by consumers and/or donors) that here, unlike in
many other areas, the standard profit motive would be over-powered and partly
misdirected.
Hansmann
emphasizes, for example, the role of ambiguous outputs (e.g., higher
educational quality, which may be hard to observe, apparently leading to the surmise
that tamping down the profit motive may lead to better results. In a very small piece that I once wrote in
this area, I made the additional point that the substitute motivation is
somewhat of a black box, which we fill in based on our empirical beliefs
concerning the motivations and utility functions of likely nonprofit
actors. This may be why, for example, we
don’t observe nonprofit auto repair shops.
Their being nonprofit might mitigate concern that they were using
asymmetric information to fool us into overpaying for stuff we don’t need, but
there is no theory of altruistically minded nonprofit auto repair workers who
would love and respect the process as much as we academics try to respect effective
teaching and good scholarship.
Substitute direct
political accountability for the profit motive, and independent experts or
professionals for nonprofit actors in a charity, and you get a parallel
scenario analytically.
(b) Analogy to
the Financial Accounting Standards Board (FASB) and the specification of
generally accepted accounting principles (GAAP) – Suppose Congress
instructed the Treasury to define taxable income, basing it on economic income
but subject to reasonable administrative concerns, including use of the
realization requirement where Treasury thought it appropriate. Full stop, subject only to whatever provision
Congress separately made for the design and use of tax preferences.
Would this be a
good thing? I am inclined to think so if
the Treasury in turn delegated the task to an insulated professional
agency. But admittedly this is just a
surmise – if Congress did this (which it won’t), then we would find out how
well or poorly it worked.
One reason for
thinking that it might be a good thing (leaving aside that it will never
happen) is the analogy to FASB and GAAP.
FASB is a somewhat independent and politically insulated agency under the
itself-somewhat-independent Securities and Exchange Commission, and it uses its
GAAP rules to define financial accounting income.
Most accountants
whom I know – and there also are arguably supportive empirical studies –
believe that GAAP, financial reporting, and the quality of the information provided
to investors by reported earnings would be a lot worse if Congress meddled a
lot more than it does in the process. On
the few occasions when Congress has intervened (e.g., when Senator Lieberman,
in the late 1990s, successfully bullied them into dropping plans for treating
executive stock options as deductible), there is a view that generally or
typically it has made things worse.
This naturally
inclines one to speculate that similar delegation with respect to defining
taxable income would likely be a good thing, if it was done right. But obviously we don’t know for sure, and an
experiment permitting us to find out remains highly unlikely. I could only see it happening if the U.S.
federal income tax became far less important and prominent than it is today
(e.g., as tariffs were once a central concern of Congressional policymaking and
then ceased to be such).
No comments:
Post a Comment