Yesterday at the Colloquium on
High-End Inequality, Alan Viard from the American Enterprise Institute
discussed portions of his recent book (with Robert Carroll), Progressive Consumption Taxation: The X-TaxRevisited.
Here are summaries of my
thoughts regarding the first two topics that I aimed to discuss. As it happened, we never got to Topic 2
(which shows that we had plenty to talk about).
1. For / against the progressive
consumption tax
My two
colleagues in leading the colloquium discussion both support shifting from the
existing income tax to a progressive consumption tax – but for very different
reasons! I had been thinking that their reasons for supporting it were wholly
inconsistent – but upon reflection (and discussion) have concluded that they
are instead merely entirely distinct, and potentially complementary.
Alan Viard: He
starts from assuming that we need a general revenue system founded on ability to
pay, and that this might be either an income tax or a consumption tax. Both
burden work, but income taxation also burdens future consumption relative to
current consumption. It thereby inefficiently deters saving. Plus, in practice enormous complexity (and
undermining of objectives) results from the full playout of the realization
requirement.
In
evaluating a consumption tax, Viard emphasizes that, in principal, deferral of the
tax (via saving instead of immediately consuming) does not reduce the expected
liability in present value, so long as tax rates are constant.
To
illustrate, say we have a flat 30% (tax-exclusive) consumption tax that will
remain in place indefinitely. Adam and
Barbara each consume $100K this year, so each pays $30K of current-year
consumption tax, But Adam also has
$100M of savings (Barbara has none).
A
current-year-focused income tax advocate might ask: How can it be fair to
charge both of them the same tax, when Barbara’s ability to pay is so much
greater? But a consumption tax advocate
might respond: Adam would have paid an additional $30M of tax if he had
consumed all his savings this year. But
by not doing so, he merely deferred it at the market interest rate, whatever
that might be. Thus, the present value
of the tax on this wealth is $30M whether he saves it for a year, a century, or
a millennium. So the consumption tax does
require him to pay more, as it should based on ability-to-pay – one simply
needs a longer time frame to make the appropriate comparison. All we need to assume, to reach this
conclusion, is a constant tax rate and realization at some point – or that indefinite deferral is effectively no
better than realization at some point.
An
income tax is likely to be more progressive than a consumption tax if they have
the same rate structure, because higher-income individuals generally save a
higher percentage of their resources than poorer individuals. But we can replace the lost progressivity from
changing the tax base from income tax to consumption by making the new tax
rates nominally higher and more progressive.
Again,
all this is what I take to be the Viard view (although I agree with most of
it); now on to the Robert Frank view.
Robert Frank: He questions
the need for an ability-to-pay tax until we’ve exhausted all taxes on negative externalities. For example, we might meet at least a portion
of our revenue needs by properly taxing pollution, carbon, congestion, etc.
But
the taxes on negative externalities that Frank favors include a luxury tax for
the high-end. The aim here is to address
expenditure cascades, addressed in this paper, which we discussed at the High-End Inequality Colloquium on October 28.
In
effect, he wants a high-end luxury tax, on the same grounds as pollution or
congestion taxes. But since it’s a
hopeless task to try to figure out all the items that ought to be on the luxury
tax list, he proposes instead to start levying the tax at very high annual
consumption levels.
This
might even be an add-on to the current income tax, although it also could come
out of a personal expenditure tax (PET) – i.e., an individual-level progressive
consumption tax. The very high rates
just at the top would presumably require thinking about multi-year inclusion of
consumer durables such as a home, and one might also debate whether averaging
should be allowed.
Could
a general consumption tax at lower rate brackets be justified on externality
grounds, rather than just under ability to pay principles? For Frank, the answer is potentially yes, but
this would require a separate critique of keeping-up-with-the-Joneses style
lateral positional wars via consumption.
Frank
also posits that the luxury tax wouldn’t greatly reduce high-end labor supply,
and does not posit adverse effects from unequal wealth-holding. His target is unequal current consumption,
based on the analysis of expenditure cascades from the top on down.
My comments & concerns:
1) Bob
Frank posits negative externalities from high-end inequality solely via the consumption
pathway. But what if there are also negative
externalities from high-end wealth-holding?
Suppose that Wilkinson-Pickett adverse effects on health and on social
gradient ills were found to be increased by wealth inequality alone, even
controlling for current consumption levels.
2) As
a matter of political economy, will progressive consumption tax rates (whether
under the Bradford X-tax or the PET) be high enough? The political process
sometimes over-focuses on marginal rates, without regard to the tax base or
actual effective rates.
3) Is
savings, reached by the income tax but not the consumption tax, a tag of
ability? If so, then under standard optimal
income tax theory, including it in the tax base can improve the available
tradeoff between distributional gain and efficiency loss.
4) On
more of a technical point, is the personal expenditure tax (PET) more
administratively friendly to highish rates than the X-tax?
2. Inheritance
The conventional wisdom holds
that, if you favor consumption taxation, then logically it’s at least against
the grain to favor estate and gift and/or inheritance taxation. But I disagree.
The above logic is inescapable
if one thinks of multi-generational family dynasties as if they were extremely
long-lived individuals. But they aren’t –
parent and child, bequestor and bequestee, are not in fact the same person.
Henry Simons famously argued for
double-taxing gifts and bequests. No
deduction to the donor, full inclusion for the done (leaving aside
administrative arguments re. small items, and perhaps set of internal transactions
within a household).
This was an argument about
consumption, not income. And whether or
not one buys his result, the logic of saying it triggered consumption by both
was clearly correct. If I make a gift,
including an altruistically minded bequest, then clearly I get utility from it,
no less than if I had instead spent my $$ on vacation travel or a
restaurant. (Accidental bequests are different,
but there it’s efficient to tax them if we posit that they were precautionary
saving, but the owner had no bequest motive and ended up not needing them
precautionarily.)
So as a matter of judging
individual welfare in ability-to-pay terms, if I give a $1M gift to my kids,
this is $1M worth of consumption by me and
by them. Double-taxing it would merely
match the fact that there was double consumption.
Why wouldn’t we want to adopt the
Simons solution? Not because it is
logically wrong in defining ability to pay – but rather because we don’t like
the policy outcome. As the literature
discusses, there is an “altruistic externality” here. I valued my enjoyment of the kids’
consumption at $1M, but I didn’t value their
enjoyment at a separate $1M. By
contrast, if I bought a standard consumption item for $1M the total welfare
gained would be just $1M.
This suggests tax-favoring gifts
and bequests for policy reasons, relative to the Simons baseline. Taxing them “just once” is a salient,
prominent, intuitive, and relatively simple way of getting to this result, but
it doesn’t inherently get the incentive exactly right.
Now suppose we are worried about
unequal wealth-holding when there is extreme high-end inequality. One might consider addressing this through a
wealth tax, but one is in the ballpark if one does this periodically, such as
by targeting gifts and bequests. So now, where there’s impact on high-end inequality,
we might want to move towards taxing gifts and bequests less favorably than
under the “tax it once” baseline.
True, in that scenario it’s
really just a mechanism for a periodic wealth tax, with the tax on gifts
needing to accompany that on bequests so it can’t be avoided via transfers to
younger or healthier individuals. Basing
it on gifts and bequests as such would merely be opportunistic. But now suppose that one’s high-end
inequality concerns are triggered by dynastic wealth transmission, unequal
opportunities in life, etc. Then the
gratuitous transfer, not the wealth-holding, might indeed be worthy of direct
focus.
My point here is not to sketch
out the policy upshot, but just to suggest that (a) there is really no logical tension
between favoring enactment of a progressive consumption tax to replace the
income tax, and wanting to tax gifts and bequests, plus (b) if one is uneasy
about the prospects for a progressive consumption tax to be progressive enough,
a tax on gifts and bequests may help to address that problem.
No comments:
Post a Comment