Our two papers for this week were by
Kate Pickett and Richard Wilkinson (available here and http://www.law.nyu.edu/sites/default/files/upload_documents/EJSP%20WilkPick%20final.pdf), Pickett was kind enough to fly over from York University in northeast England to present and discuss this work.
1.
Causal claim
The papers
examine evidence regarding the empirical relationship between income inequality on the one
hand, and health/ behavioral ills that have a social gradient on the other
hand. (“Social gradient” means that,
within a given society, they tend to be negatively correlated with income.)
The following ills are
positively correlated with a society’s measured income inequality (e.g., based
on Gini coefficients or the level of the 80th percentile versus the
20th percentile, among alternative measures that can be used): lower
life expectancy, higher infant mortality, worse educational
performance by children, and the frequency of teenage births, homicides, other
violence, imprisonment rates, mental illness, drug and alcohol addiction, and obesity.
Likewise,
measures of social trust and economic mobility are negatively correlated with
income inequality. All this, of course,
is based on adjusting for income levels.
And the ills are positively correlated with income inequality even among
the wealthy in a given society.
An initial
question is: should we accept the correlation?
It’s based on an enormous weight of evidence from different societies
and time periods (all involving recent decades, however). It really seems to far too much evidence of correlation
to ignore or reject.
Second
question: how do we explain it? When A
is shown to be correlated empirically with B, we can posit either that A causes
B, or that B causes A, or that something else causes both.
Wilkinson
and Pickett posit that income inequality causes the social bads. They
argue that this is intuitively plausible, reflecting that we are competitive
social beings, equipped for both egalitarian and hierarchical relationship
patterns, but happier and less anxious in the former (which seems to have
prevailed in real evolutionary time from the very distant past until the rise
of agriculture only a few thousand years ago).
But they also argue that it best fits the evidence.
What
about the theory that the bads cause income inequality? Among the counters to such a view is the fact
that, in the data, there tends to be lag from a given society’s rise in income
inequality to its experiencing greater social gradient health and behavioral
ills.
What
about the theory that something else explains both? Suppose we point the figure at culture – e.g.,
positing that something about U.S. and U.K. culture make us prime hosts both
for income inequality and for social gradient ills (e.g., from having highly
competitive cultures). Wilkinson and
Pickett note, however, that the evidence fits their causal theory pretty well,
whereas it’s difficult to make it work in terms of cultural fits. For example, why should Scandinavian countries
resemble Japan, and why should Spain be so unlike the (historically far more
unequal) Portugal when their cultures are so different?
I am
strongly inclined to accept both the claimed correlation and the causal explanation
that Wilkinson and Pickett offer. But there
is going to be an ongoing social science debate about this, which I believe
their side will decisively win.
2.
Issues raised by accepting the causal claim
a)
Is it culturally or ideologically specific to the present?
I wonder if inequality today is
different from inequality in the past.
The data obviously doesn’t go nearly far back enough to test this as one
might like,
Consider the medieval epoch in
Europe, during which inequality and hierarchy were considered entirely natural,
by analogy to the family. Familial hierarchy running from parents to children
is indeed a mental module that humans appear to have. And might it be generalized under propitious
(for it) circumstances? Consider cats, naturally feral yet able to adapt their
kitten-to-mother mental module to the circumstances of modern pet culture.
Not to be too whimsical here,
but could today’s problems with inequality – not by any means to idealize it in
the past – have something to do with the difficulty of adapting the familial
module to a mass society, plus the consequences of experiencing it in a modern
capitalist context where it has become intertwined with meritocratic ideology?
b)
What is the “bad” that affects people?
The paper discusses
“status threat.” This brings to mind nature documentaries and books about
baboon society, full of violence from above and the continual need to defend
oneself from rivals below.
Maybe not entirely
a bad metaphor – baboon society is said to have considerable resemblances to
ours – but in a modern social context, would the “bad” result more from
vertical status differences, or from uncertainty and ambiguity in relative
rankings?
Robert Frank would
be inclined to shelve “status threat” explanations that seem to sound in
bullying and resentment, in favor of positional externalities from consumption
levels. There verticality might potentially make things worse, depending on how
people judge the relevance for themselves of consumption levels way above their
own. But this need not be a case of
either-or.
c)
Different kinds of inequality
I’ve been emphasizing the differences
between high-end and low-end in equality (plutocracy versus poverty). The evidence adduced concededly does not as
yet do much to address that issue.
Thus, for example, when one of
the papers notes that high-inequality U.S. states have more social gradient
ills than their peers, the former are a mix of the likes of New York and the
District of Columbia, with the likes of Mississippi and Louisiana. These issues
are important to address when one is thinking about policy responses to the
negative social effects of inequality.
d)
Policy implications
i) The pollution analogy.
Inequality appears to generate negative
externalities, in a manner analogous to that caused by pollution. How should this shape our responses? Suppose we are thinking in terms of a
Pigovian pollution tax.
In the canonical Pigovian case (with
the full information that’s possible in a textbook example), we know what marginal
disvalue, expressed in monetary terms, the people adversely affected by
pollution face on each additional quantum of it. And while of course we won’t precisely know
this in any real world example, at least it gives us a useful framework
for thinking about the proper design of
a pollution tax.
In the case of inequality, we
don’t know which types matter the most, whether the marginal harm rises in any
sort of continuous fashion, or really anything about how best to price it. Also, whereas in the Pigovian pollution tax
we have consumers whose current utility functions and circumstances determine
the cost, in the inequality case we’re asking how people would relatively value
their wellbeing under two completely different scenarios. They cannot easily judge this, even in theory.
So even if one comes out in
favor of fiscal measures addressing inequality due to its negative externalities,
we don’t have a great model available regarding how best to do this.
Of course, this is not the first
time that we have faced such a problem in instrument design – as discussed, for
example here (in an article on taxation and the financial sector that I
coauthored with Doug Shackelford and Joel Slemrod).
ii) High-end versus low-end
inequality
I have been arguing for some
time that we need to think about high-end versus low-end to a degree
distinctly.
One reason is that the policy
tools one would use to address them differ.
Low-end inequality may be addressed in large part through public
spending on public goods, along with consumer goods that are necessities and/or
potential areas for market failure. For
example, as Ed Kleinbard and others have noted, the tax system is generally
less on point here than ensuring people of good quality healthcare, education,
childcare, transportation options, etcetera.
For high-end inequality, by
contrast, we may be inclined to think primarily in terms of high-end marginal
tax rates (and the tax base), inheritance taxation, the scope and term of IP
protection, corporate governance, rules for the financial sector, etc.
A second reason for
distinguishing between high-end and low-end inequality is that our rationales
for wanting to address them may be quite different.
With respect to poverty, anyone
equipped with basic beneficence should care about alleviating it, in order to
make people better off. But concern
about plutocracy requires further motivation, since the aim is surely not to
make a bunch of people worse-off.
Under standard public economics
and optimal income tax models, in which people care only about own consumption,
the declining marginal utility of material resources provides the only
rationale for concern about plutocracy (although there might also be ad hoc egalitarian
weighting of a social welfare function).
But if harms are being caused, the analysis may change dramatically –
including by rebutting the view that one would never want to set a high-end tax
rate above its revenue-maximizing level.
Against this background, the Wilkinson-Pickett evidence, in my view, does more to influence how we should think about high-end than low-end inequality, even though it is pertinent to both.
Against this background, the Wilkinson-Pickett evidence, in my view, does more to influence how we should think about high-end than low-end inequality, even though it is pertinent to both.
1 comment:
I'm glad you're giving your impression of papers like this, in the blog. It's useful for you, I expect, to write down notes on papers, but it's nice for a few other people who happen across it too--- so keep doing it!
Post a Comment