Perhaps as soon as next week, we will reach the topic of how the
Internal Revenue Code treats gambling losses. In brief, what the Code does is
deny deductions for net gambling losses during the year. This is probably best
rationalized as a proxy for the fact that people - say, gambling in a casino or
at the racetrack for an evening here and there - may gamble despite expecting
to lose money, viewing it as an entertainment activity. E.g., Person 1 goes to
the theater at a cost of $100, because he or she likes to attend plays. Person
2 goes to the casino, expecting to lose $100 but anticipating a sufficiently fun
time at the tables while this is happening. In the case where this expectation
is precisely satisfied, these two cases look pretty much the same, and the tax
law treats them the same by denying the deduction in both cases. (Leaving aside
the issue of gambling gains on a different evening, against which the $100
gambling loss could be deducted.)
This is of course a bit of an arbitrary rule. And it has the odd
implication that if, say, I bet you $100 on the outcome of the Super Bowl (and
neither of us does any other gambling during the year), then as a matter of
income tax law the winner has $100 of taxable income, while the loser has a
nondeductible $100 loss. Plus, if I lose $200 rather than $100, than I'm actually worse off - perhaps emotionally as well as economically - yet the rule, by denying any deduction, in effect treats me as if I had enjoyed $200 of consumption value.
It strikes me that the taxation of gambling is a more interesting topic theoretically
than it is as a practical matter (where rough and ready rules such as what we
have today are certainly close enough for government work,).
To illustrate a part of what I have in mind, suppose there were 3
types of gamblers, each wholly distinguishable from the other two and known
both to themselves and the authorities. Suppose further that everyone was
perfectly rational, given his or her preferences, and that there were no
administrative issues of measurement (as well as none of identification), and
also that there were no borderline or mixed-motive cases. Then it is plausible
that each should be treated under a wholly separate regime, as follows.
PLEASE NOTE, HOWEVER, THAT WHAT FOLLOWS BELOW IS A THOUGHT
EXPERIMENT TO TEASE OUT THE SEEMING IMPLICATIONS OF VARIOUS IDEAS - NOT AN ACTUAL PROPOSAL FOR THE FAR
MESSIER REAL WORLD!
Case 1: Taxpayer rationally expects to break even, but wants to
bet because taking on the risk is fun: As an example of what I have in mind here, people
generally hate and try to avoid the sensation of free fall, yet they also have been known to stand on hour-long
lines to ride scary rollercoasters. Suppose, analogously, that I bet $100 on the
Super Bowl, despite ordinarily being risk-averse, because it will add to my
excitement and pleasure in watching the game. (Or for that matter, I may bet
the money on the Patriots as a psychic hedge, because I'm otherwise rooting
against them.)
Here, under the strict assumptions that I am making, there is an
argument for excluding both gains and losses. There is no reason to
tax-penalize the activity, as between consenting adults who are in fact on
equal terms. (I'm ruling out the scenario where one is a more skillful bettor
than the other, hence should actually expect to win on average.)
The standard insurance argument for income (or consumption) taxation
might suggest symmetrically including gains and deducting losses. Then one
might raise the Domar-Musgrave point, to the effect that the bettors could
offset this by scaling up the bet. E.g., if they want to bet $100, but gains
are included and losses are deducted (with loss refundability if needed), they
can get there anyway if their tax rates are the same. E.g., if the
counterparties both face 33% marginal rates, then instead of betting $100
without tax consequences, they bet $150 with, and get to exactly the same
place.
Is it unfortunate that they can do this? Not at all, under my
assumptions. The income tax as insurance responds, in rational actor scenarios, purely to undesired risk (e.g., from the "ability lottery" or from having
under-diversified human capital by reason of needing to specialize). But
here, by assumption, people are rationally doing what they want and like.
So, while their presumed ability to offset the undesired "insurance"
suggests that maybe it just doesn't matter, ignoring the bet leads directly to
the desired result. There is no motivation for making them adjust (even if it
does no harm under the assumption that it's easily done, and indeed that in any event they are betting given the degree of mandatory insurance).
Case 2: Taxpayer rationally expects to win, and bets in order to
make money: Suppose
we have a card-counter in the game of 21, or else a really good poker player, who bets so as to make
money, just as other people go to the office in order to earn a salary. Now we
face the standard case of risky business investment, in which gains should be
taxed and losses deducted (including with loss refundability). Real world loss
limitation rules, such as the fact that one cannot use net operating losses to
get direct federal payouts at the applicable marginal rate, arguably reflect measurement
concerns - we may fear that people are creating tax shelter losses rather than
reporting real economic ones. But I have ruled all that out of bounds for purposes
of my hypothetical.
This regime of including/taxing gains while deducting/refunding
(at the tax rate) losses provides arguably desirable insurance through the tax
system in at least two senses. First, it in effect redistributes from better
gamblers to worse ones, consistent with the ability lottery scenario where
people differ in "wage rate" and can't insure against this privately
due to adverse selection. Second, as with any other risky business investment,
it provides desired insurance that might otherwise be unavailable. To
illustrate this point, I used to know a card counter who went to casinos when
he could spare the time, solely to make money. He hated the short-term
variation, which in fact was high enough that he could go, say, from plus
$35,000 to minus $20,000 (with gambler's ruin potentially looming) in the
course of a few hours. He really just wanted to earn his expected return -
while also needing to manage his stress over avoiding detection (which required making
some deliberately bad bets, so as to throw off the watchers employed by the gambling establishment).
It's worth noting a further assumption that may be needed here to
make this approach attractive. Normally we are glad that people are willing to
engage in risky activity that has a net expected payoff. But in the case of
gambling, the gains are other people's losses. If one thinks of this as
rent-seeking or negative externalities, the approach I'm suggesting arguably is
undermined. But under my assumptions, as opposed to those that it would be
reasonable to apply in the real world, this is not an issue. After all, no one
is systematically losing under my gambling hypotheticals unless, as I discuss next, they are deliberately (and rationally) undertaking it as a consumption activity.
Case 3: Taxpayer rationally expects to lose, but happily gambles
anyway for the entertainment value: Suppose again that we have two people. The first spends $100 to go to the
theater, anticipating an enjoyable show. The second spends a few hours in the
casino, expecting to lose $100, likewise regarding this as a fun way to spend
the evening. And suppose that the fun comes out of the process of the gambling
itself - unlike in Case 1 above, let us assume that it's not from wanting to
bear risk as such.
The theatergoer faces, of course, the risk that the play will
prove to be a dud (and hence revealed ex post not to have been worth $100, much less a
couple of hours that one will never get back). But at least the financial cost is known in
advance. One certainly could imagine the gambler thinking about the evening in much the same
way, and thus regretting that in fact it's possible to lose a lot more than the expected $100 (or to
have to end the night of gambling sooner than expected).
While we may be starting here to leave far behind the actual
psychology behind gambling (which surely includes the hope of winning against the odds), one could, if one liked, conceptually divide the gambler's results into a
"consumption component" and an "investment
component." From this standpoint, one might say that the above
gambler has what ought to be a nondeductible consumption outlay, in the amount
of the $100 expected cost, along with investment variation above or below that
which "ought" to be deducted or included, as the case may be.
E.g., suppose I actually break even when I ought to have lost $100. Under
the hypothetical approach, I would have $100 of taxable income. (After all, I'm
$100 better-off than my otherwise identical peer who actually did lose exactly
$100.) Or suppose I have a rotten night and lose $200, even though I actually
should have expected to lose only $100. Now I have a deductible $100 loss.
Note that, with perfect knowledge (by the gambler and the
government) of the expected loss, we don't get into Domar-Musgrave adjustments
here. If I change how I am
actually betting, then I change the expected loss.
If one revised the treatment of Case 1 so that gains were included
and losses deducted (rather than both being ignored), it would be
receiving the same treatment as Case 3 (given that the expected loss in Case 1
is zero). So those two start to collapse together, once one picks at the
examples a bit.
Likewise, once we see that, in Case 2, it's really the positive
expected return that one might want to tax (as "ability"), one might start feeling inclined to ask whether, in Case 3, one should want to treat lousy gamblers, who
rapidly accumulate large expected losses, less favorably than the more skillful
(though still loss-expecting) gamblers, who are able on average to slow the bleeding, and thus to gamble less unprofitably or for longer. This might
start to push us in the direction of wanting to treat really bad gamblers more
favorably than good ones, e.g., by not simply benchmarking them off the larger expected losses
that reflect their lower ability in this respect. This would in effect be insurance against being the sort of gambler who is bad enough at it to have a larger than typical expected loss. (And of course I am assuming that the difference here is in ability, not effort - we're in the same realm as a wage tax that discourages work if our making this adjustment discourages people from learning how to become better gamblers.)
But here, at last, is the ACTUAL takeaway that I derive from all
this: Theory, at least of very simple kinds, is more tractable than reality. It's easier to say where greatly simplified hypotheticals would lead us under particular normative views, than to reach confident judgments about the real world, in which multiple, conflicting such hypotheticals may each be more than 0% true, and yet each push us in very different directions.
No comments:
Post a Comment