Yesterday at the colloquium, Zach Liscow presented his paper
“Democratic Law and Economics.” Before getting directly to the paper, I think it’s
useful to put it in a broader context that will be familiar to some
readers but perhaps not others.
The law and economics movement in law schools, which got
going in earnest about 40 years ago, in its early stages made a lot of strides
using an approach that some call “Econ 101ism.” As per Noah Smith:
“We all know
basically what 101ism says. Markets are efficient. Firms are competitive.
Partial-equilibrium supply and demand describes most things. Demand curves
slope down and supply curves slope up. Only one curve shifts at a time. No
curve is particularly inelastic or elastic; all are somewhere in the middle
(straight lines with slopes of 1 and -1 on a blackboard). Etc.”
Econ 101ism was a step forward for legal scholarship, but
not a step far enough. One had to understand what the logic of a standard
neoclassical analysis implied, but the next step required recognizing that its
assumptions might not always hold, and then asking what that would imply. It’s
a great orienting tool, but its seductive power to purport to answer so many
questions, from so parsimonious a starting point, can over-excite the
incautious if they forget that they need to take that next step of testing the
accuracy and sufficiency of its assumptions.
A more recent trend in what one might call tax or public
finance law and economics involves using a very simple model that purports to
answer lots of questions. The Atkinson-Stiglitz theorem holds (within the
specified terms of its model): “Where the utility function is separable between
labor and all commodities, no indirect taxes need be employed.”
Take the Mirrlees model, in which we want to base the tax on
ability but can only measure earnings, so we impose a labor income tax that is equivalent
to a uniform commodity tax. (Wages are used to buy commodities, and in a
one-period model one spends it all currently.) Atkinson-Stiglitz asks whether
one might get a better outcome by having non-uniform commodity taxes, e.g.,
taxing luxuries at a higher rate than the rest. It shows that, within its
terms, the answer to this question is NO unless some commodities are leisure
substitutes or complements. E.g., if I work more, I may substitute restaurant
meals for buying groceries (leisure substitute). Or if I work less I might want
to buy a telescope so I can spend hours stargazing (leisure complement). But
absent any of that, the uniform commodity tax is best.
Suppose one thought that taxing yachts at a higher rate
would have an admitted efficiency cost (discouraging yacht choice vs. other
consumption), but also an efficiency gain (raising revenue that permits one to
lower the labor income tax rate). So isn’t there a tradeoff, with even an
implication that there might be a net efficiency gain, since multiple smaller
distortions are often better than just one large one?
Answer: No. You still have to work to get the $$ to buy a
yacht, and working is just a way of getting to buy things. So one is still,
roughly speaking, discouraging labor supply as much as before, plus one is now
also distorting commodity choice. Hence there is now “double distortion”
without mitigation of the prior distortion.
Leading figures in tax or public finance law and economics
(e.g., Kaplow and Shavell) have shown how broad Atkinson-Stiglitz’s
implications might be. For example, one can think of an income tax as imposing higher
commodity taxes on future consumption than current consumption, creating double
distortion (discouragement of saving) without any mitigation of a consumption
tax’s admitted discouragement of work and market consumption. Hence, case
closed for the income tax? Yes unless there is more to the analysis, but the
point (as with Econ 101ism) is that there might be. (And for what it’s worth,
neither Atkinson nor Stiglitz agrees that based on their theorem one should
prefer consumption taxation to income taxation.)
Likewise, case closed (within the analysis) with regard to
using “legal rules” instead of the “tax system” to redistribute. Here the “tax
system” means, not Title 26 of the Internal Revenue Code, but a labor income
tax plus demogrant. “Legal rules” means pretty much anything else. E.g.,
income-conditioned speeding tickets, like they have in Finland. Product
liability or tort rules that favor consumers or accident victims on the ground
that they’re generally poorer. Mandatory contract clauses to protect tenants.
Inducing corporate managers to optimize for “stakeholders,” not just
shareholders, under a progressive redistributive rationale.
Under the view, using any of those types of vehicles to
address distributional concerns about rich vs. poor merely yields double
distortion. You’re still discouraging labor supply, insofar as becoming rich
subjects you to expected unfavorable treatment under those rules. Plus, you’re
departing from the efficient choice in those areas, which makes things worse
overall than if one had just used the labor income tax to address
distributional concerns.
The takeaway from this analysis was and is: All analysis of
“legal rules” and government policies outside the labor income tax should be
driven PURELY by considerations of efficiency. Leave redistribution purely to
the “tax system.”
This view has been highly influential in legal scholarship,
and also perhaps in regulatory policy as actually done. But it has inspired
pushback, both on theoretical grounds (based on whether the underlying
assumptions are sufficiently accurate and complete) and in light of concerns
that, in practice, it leads to too little progressivity if policymakers adopt
it in the realm of “legal rules,” but not when designing the tax system.
This, anyway, is vital background for discussing Liscow’s
“Democratic Law and Economics,” to which I will turn directly in my next
blogpost.
-->
1 comment:
You want to know what you spouse does with their phones,you want to know what happens when you are away from home,do you need a classified hacker to hack,you need to upgrade your credit score and delete your criminal records,contact victorhacks@gmail.com
Post a Comment