I have an article in today's Tax Notes, entitled "Evaluating the Case for 1986-Style Tax Reform." You can download it here.
This is the piece, expressing skepticism about the degree of policy gain that would result from lowering the corporate tax rate plus broadening the business tax base, that I presented at the Boston College-Tax Analysts Conference on Reforming Entity Taxation on October 10, 2014. As per earlier blog posts, you can find slides for the talk here, and an account of the day's proceedings (from a Tax Notes article by Amy Elliott) here.
Monday, December 15, 2014
Wednesday, December 03, 2014
Spring 2015 Tax Policy Colloquium
The time is now drawing near - January 20, or just under 7 weeks away - when I'll be co-leading my/the twentieth (!) NYU Tax Policy Colloquium. I've previously posted the speaker schedule, and noted that my co-convenor will be Alan Viard of the American Enterprise Institute, but the following is a first-time-posted full schedule with tentative paper titles (many of them placeholders and/or subject to change):
SCHEDULE FOR 2015 NYU TAX POLICY
COLLOQUIUM
(All
sessions meet on Tuesdays from 4-5:50 pm in Vanderbilt 208, NYU Law School)
1. January 20 – Brigitte Madrian, Harvard
Kennedy School. “Does Front-Loading Taxation Increase Savings? Evidence from Roth 401(k)
Introductions.”
2. January 27 – David Kamin, NYU Law
School. "In
Good Times and Bad: Designing Legislation That Responds to Fiscal
Uncertainty."
3. February 3
– Kimberly Blanchard, Weil, Gotshal & Manges. "The Tax Significance of Legal Personality:
A U.S. View."
4. February 10 – Linda Sugin, Fordham Law
School. “Invisible Taxpayers.”
5. February 24 – Eric Toder, Urban
Institute. “What the United States Can Learn From Other Countries’ Territorial Tax
Systems.”
6. March 3 – Ruth Mason, University of
Virginia Law School. “Citizenship
Taxation.”
7. March 10 – George Yin, University of
Virginia Law School. “Protecting Taxpayers from Congressional
Lawbreaking.”
8. March 24 – Leigh Osofsky, University
of Miami School of Law, “Tax Law Non-Enforcement.”
9.
March 31 – Shu-Yi Oei, Tulane Law School. “Human Equity? Regulating the New Income Share Agreements.”
10. April 7 – Lillian Mills, University of
Texas Business School. “Topics [to be
determined] in Financial Reporting and Corporate Tax Compliance.”
11. April 14 – Lawrence Zelenak, Duke
University School of Law. “Up in the Air
over the Taxation of Frequent Flyer Benefits: the American, Canadian, and
Australian Experiences.”
12. April 21 – David Albouy, University of
Illinois Economics Department. “Should
we be taxed out of our homes? Leisure and housing as complements and optimal
taxation.”
13. April 28 – David Schizer, Columbia Law
School. “Tax and Energy Policy.”
14. May 5 – Gregg Polsky, University of
North Carolina School of Law, "Private Equity
Tax Games and Their Implications for Tax Practitioners, Enforcers, and
Reformers."
Tuesday, November 18, 2014
You take what you can get
Harry Grubert has published a thoughtful review of my book, Fixing U.S. International Taxation, in the latest issue of the National Tax Journal. It's a good read, not just for anything it says about my book, but perhaps even more so for its addressing some topics (such as formulary apportionment) that I mention in the book, but that have been been of especial long-term interest to him.
Although Harry is an economist and I'm a lawyer, he might actually have preferred a more "lawyer"-type book, whereas I wrote a conceptually more "economist"-type one. Thus, take what I consider to be an important conceptual advance from the book and my related prior articles: distinguishing between (a) the tax burden on outbound investment and (b) the incentive to minimize foreign taxes. To me, this is inherently important, in the sense that it relates to clear thinking.
Harry agrees that I have advanced the ball on thinking about U.S. companies' incentives with respect to foreign taxes, and that this may be "particularly useful" to keep in mind as the international tax reform process goes forward. But he notes that there are also plenty of other important issues in international taxation relating to lots of margins. Some might even have greater practical importance than this one. (As I would agree.)
Harry's focus is thus, in a sense, more practically grounded than mine - as it should be, given how much he knows about the empirical interrelationships, across decades, of multiple moving pieces. But there is certainly room for both types of approaches. I very much look forward to our further exchanges on international tax topics.
Although Harry is an economist and I'm a lawyer, he might actually have preferred a more "lawyer"-type book, whereas I wrote a conceptually more "economist"-type one. Thus, take what I consider to be an important conceptual advance from the book and my related prior articles: distinguishing between (a) the tax burden on outbound investment and (b) the incentive to minimize foreign taxes. To me, this is inherently important, in the sense that it relates to clear thinking.
Harry agrees that I have advanced the ball on thinking about U.S. companies' incentives with respect to foreign taxes, and that this may be "particularly useful" to keep in mind as the international tax reform process goes forward. But he notes that there are also plenty of other important issues in international taxation relating to lots of margins. Some might even have greater practical importance than this one. (As I would agree.)
Harry's focus is thus, in a sense, more practically grounded than mine - as it should be, given how much he knows about the empirical interrelationships, across decades, of multiple moving pieces. But there is certainly room for both types of approaches. I very much look forward to our further exchanges on international tax topics.
Monday, November 17, 2014
I forgot to post this a couple of weeks ago
Posing with Lee Sheppard before a discussion of Ed Kleinbard's book, on Halloween at NYU Law School.
My own paper presentation at NTA
In addition to commenting on the Green-Phillips paper noted in the preceding blog entry, I also presented one of my recent papers, forthcoming in the Connecticut Law Review, entitled "Multiple Myopias, Multiple Selves, and the Under-Saving Problem." Jason Seligman of Ohio State offered thoughtful and helpful comments. This was my first, and perhaps last, presentation of this paper, which I finished early last summer, as consumer demand has generally been higher for my Piketty paper (as well as for a short piece on corporate tax reform that I will post on SSRN after it appears in Tax Notes next month).
A link of the slides for my talk is available here, and a link for the paper is available here.
Slide 5 contains a little table that ought to have been in my paper, and that will indeed be (with some expansion) in the final version. Here is an initial expansion over what I had in the slide:
A link of the slides for my talk is available here, and a link for the paper is available here.
Slide 5 contains a little table that ought to have been in my paper, and that will indeed be (with some expansion) in the final version. Here is an initial expansion over what I had in the slide:
Table 1 - Summary of (Some) Possible Explanations for Low Retirement Saving
Cause for low Representative Potential
retirement saving Figure Policy Response
Naïve myopia Grasshopper Mandatory
saving?
Sophisticated myopia Odysseus (Sirens) Opportunity to choose (and
lock
in) saving pre-temptation?
Regret aversion re. Fantasy sports player Good defaults, require active choice?
"active" choice who
won’t trade
Procrastination Hamlet Good
defaults, require active choice?
Inattentiveness Voters Good
defaults, require attention?
Multiple selves Sybil ???
Comment I gave at the NTA Annual Meeting
At the recently-concluded NTA Annual Meeting, I was asked to offer a brief comment on a nice paper by Richard Green and Mark Phillips of USC, entitled "Demand for the 1%: Tax Incidence and Implications for Optimal Income Tax Rates." I myself can access a link for the paper here, but I'm not sure the link will work for readers who didn't register for the NTA conference.
Anyway, here is an approximate reconstruction of my comments:
Anyway, here is an approximate reconstruction of my comments:
Assigning me to
comment on this paper is a great example of the NTA at either its best or its worst. That’s for all of you to judge, depending on
how much value you think I add.
Reflecting the
NTA’s interdisciplinary aspirations, we have here a lawyer – that would be me –
commenting on an economics paper that is full of math, including numerous
propositions and proofs. In the words of
Martin Short, playing a Hollywood agent in a movie called The Big Picture with respect to a stack of scripts that his client
was naïvely hoping he had fully evaluated, “I read almost all of them almost
all the way through.” But perhaps I can
try to add value in a different way. In
particular, I’d like to offer six quick comments in the 5 minutes that I have
available today.
First, the paper
is interesting and important because the question it examines – how optimal tax
analysis might be affected if the incidence of a personal income tax may be
shifted, such as through effects on pre-tax wage levels – clearly matters, yet
has often been ignored. But it’s a shame
that the paper is interesting and important!
Life would certainly be easier if we could simply assume away any such
effects. The paper is convincing,
however, when it argues that we cannot necessarily do this.
Two areas in which
the literature has wrestled with
income tax incidence are the taxation of saving, and corporate income
taxation. As to the first, if the
overall level of saving doesn’t respond much to the taxation of saving – which some
evidence, admittedly not entirely conclusive, suggests – then
incidence-shifting would presumably be slight.
As to the latter, the reason we need to worry about the incidence of the
corporate tax is not that it’s paid by a legal entity – pretty clearly, that
makes it a tax on the shareholders who own the residual – but rather that its
being shifted is highly plausible, especially when national-level corporate taxes
are operating within an integrated global economy.
Second, in a
sense that the paper nicely explains, incidence-shifting with respect to
high-end wages makes the tax on them what I will call “as if lower.” If pre-tax wages at the top of the income
distribution rise in response to highly graduated rates, that partly reverses
both the intended distributional effects and the tax’s dampening effect on
labor supply. So in some respects it is
as if the tax rate were lower than if there were no incidence-shifting through
wage effects.
This causes me to
entertain the intuition that perhaps the optimal rate might turn out to be
higher, rather than lower, in the presence of wage effects, so as to get back
to approximately the same place. But in
the paper’s model it comes out the other way.
This presumably is due to how things work out with respect to the lower
99 percent of the wage distribution. It
would be nice for the paper to explain more fully what gives rise to its
result, in which wage-shifting lowers, rather than raises, the optimal rate.
Third, a question
of interest is how robust the paper’s finding would be to other inputs into the
determination of optimal tax rates.
Suppose, for example, that optimal high-end rates reflect the
policymaker’s belief that extreme high-end income or wealth inequality imposes
negative distributional externalities on other in the society. It seems plausible to me that the pattern of
effect would be similar (lowering the optimal rate relative to the case of no
wage-shifting). But given my prior
comment, I suppose I shouldn’t assume that my intuitions about how the model
works are correct.
Fourth, the paper
assumes competitive high-end wage markets, while noting that a desirable extension
might be to test the consequences of changing this assumption. Clearly, this could be important, given that
there may in fact be non-competitive wage markets at the top of the
distribution. However, one challenge in
incorporating this extension is that we don’t necessarily understand how
noncompetitive wage markets actually operate.
Suppose initially that one is extracting the maximum available rent, and
that changing the high-end tax rate won’t affect this. That’s a pretty simple case to evaluate (the
optimal rate presumably should be higher than otherwise if the pre-tax wage is
fixed), but it is only one possibility.
But suppose
instead that, say, CEO salaries set by sweetheart boards of directors are more
responsive than this. Might it
conceivably go in either direction? One
scenario is that the board restores the CEO’s after-tax position by raising the
pre-tax wage. But for an opposite
scenario, consider the claim (made, for example, by Thomas Piketty) that
lowering high-end individual marginal tax rates led to higher pretax wages for
CEOs, as it was now more worthwhile playing the entire over-compensation
game. Whether one agrees with that claim
or not, it’s a real world claim about how CEO wages respond to marginal tax
rates that might actually come out predicting that the pretax wage is lower,
not higher, if the tax rate on the CEO goes up.
But my main point here is simply that we have to understand how
particular noncompetitive wage markets work in order to be confident about how
best to extend the paper’s analysis to such settings.
Fifth, the paper
assumes away special sectoral taxes in response to noncompetitive wages in
particular settings, noting that these would present both administrative and
political economy challenges. But at
least as a political economy matter, it’s unclear if setting high wages in
particular settings where the markets aren’t functioning well would be harder
or easier than raising high rates generally.
For example, you might avoid needing to fight with the entire high-wage
sector if only some of them are having their taxes raised. My point here, however, is just to note that
political economy effects can be complicated, hard to model, and can go in
various directions.
Finally, a quick
point about the earned income tax credit or EITC. As the paper notes, if it bids down pretax
wages at the bottom of the distribution, that would partly undo the intended
distributional effects of the EITC.
Depending on one’s reasons for having the EITC, this might not be all
bad. For example, suppose that reduced
pretax wages trigger expanded low-wage employment through their supply side
effects, and that this would be desirable for other reasons (e.g., building the
workforce affiliation, skills, and habits of low-wage potential workers, in
ways those individuals have not anticipated).
This might further the EITC’s aim of increasing low-wage
employment. Then again, there might be
lots of other ripple effects on wages in the low end of the distribution that
one would want to think about. (For
example, suppose it also drove down other low-end wages.)
Again, my point
here is simply that the paper’s unavoidable embrace of new areas of
complication points the way to yet more complications that we may want to try
to add to the analysis.
In sum, this is a
good paper that should stimulate extensions and further thought.
Sunday, November 16, 2014
A defense of cats (not that they need it)
For some reason, I have been annoyedly mulling over, for a couple of weeks now, an article that appeared in Ezra Klein's Vox blog concerning cats. The case it sought to make, essentially, was "cats are bad."
Okay, I'll grant Vox the fact that cats kill a whole lot of birds. But that obviously is only outdoor cats. Our four have no chance of meeting wildlife other than creatures that we unabashedly classify as vermin if they cross the threshold into our house. (I am far more benign towards these creatures when they remain outside.)
Then there was another point I suppose I have to grant, concerning the risk of getting diseases from your cat. But lots of things that one may want to do have downside risk - and if that's dispositive, why ever leave your house or cross the street.
The point that really annoyed me in the Vox article was this section about how cats don't really love us. Although in a sense, ahem, not entirely, completely, 100 percent untrue, my thought was: How pathetic and neurotic one would have to be to find oneself thinking, about one's cats: "Do they love me? Are my feelings not fully requited? (whimper, sob)."
BTW, as I type this I have little Gary sitting on the tabletop next to the keyboard - he finds the cursor interesting and I have to save occasionally and keep him off the keyboard if I want to keep going. But I digress. Back to the "love" question.
If you are spending your life with a (human) significant other, the question of whether there is genuinely reciprocal love strikes me as rather important. But suppose instead that we are talking about a pet. Suppose that he* is beautiful, active, interesting, at times hilarious, playful, has strong feelings and distinctive personality traits, is definitely interested in you, often follows you around, sometimes likes to be petted and/or held (depending on individual feline taste), likes to rub against you sometimes (OK, granted that they also rub against the furniture), is extra friendly if he hasn't seen you for a while (this is true of ours, though not of all cats), puts you to some extent in the "mother" slot in his brain, purrs when you pet or hold him and he is in the mood, etcetera. If, despite all this, you are going to start blubbering to yourself: "But does he love me as much as I love him?," then you are way too needy. Enjoy the good things, and if that's not enough for you stick to dogs (or get yourself some helpful psychoactive medication) but recognize that it is your problem, not cats'. (BTW, I have nothing bad to say about dogs - I agree that they're great, it's just that they're a whole lot of work, especially in an urban setting.)
If cats are simply not to your taste, then fine, no quarrel here, lots of us have different tastes in various respects and yet can have mutual respect, some of my best friends don't like cats, etcetera, although I'll admit to not counting it as a point in one's favor.
*I say "he" because all four of our cats are boys.
Okay, I'll grant Vox the fact that cats kill a whole lot of birds. But that obviously is only outdoor cats. Our four have no chance of meeting wildlife other than creatures that we unabashedly classify as vermin if they cross the threshold into our house. (I am far more benign towards these creatures when they remain outside.)
Then there was another point I suppose I have to grant, concerning the risk of getting diseases from your cat. But lots of things that one may want to do have downside risk - and if that's dispositive, why ever leave your house or cross the street.
The point that really annoyed me in the Vox article was this section about how cats don't really love us. Although in a sense, ahem, not entirely, completely, 100 percent untrue, my thought was: How pathetic and neurotic one would have to be to find oneself thinking, about one's cats: "Do they love me? Are my feelings not fully requited? (whimper, sob)."
BTW, as I type this I have little Gary sitting on the tabletop next to the keyboard - he finds the cursor interesting and I have to save occasionally and keep him off the keyboard if I want to keep going. But I digress. Back to the "love" question.
If you are spending your life with a (human) significant other, the question of whether there is genuinely reciprocal love strikes me as rather important. But suppose instead that we are talking about a pet. Suppose that he* is beautiful, active, interesting, at times hilarious, playful, has strong feelings and distinctive personality traits, is definitely interested in you, often follows you around, sometimes likes to be petted and/or held (depending on individual feline taste), likes to rub against you sometimes (OK, granted that they also rub against the furniture), is extra friendly if he hasn't seen you for a while (this is true of ours, though not of all cats), puts you to some extent in the "mother" slot in his brain, purrs when you pet or hold him and he is in the mood, etcetera. If, despite all this, you are going to start blubbering to yourself: "But does he love me as much as I love him?," then you are way too needy. Enjoy the good things, and if that's not enough for you stick to dogs (or get yourself some helpful psychoactive medication) but recognize that it is your problem, not cats'. (BTW, I have nothing bad to say about dogs - I agree that they're great, it's just that they're a whole lot of work, especially in an urban setting.)
If cats are simply not to your taste, then fine, no quarrel here, lots of us have different tastes in various respects and yet can have mutual respect, some of my best friends don't like cats, etcetera, although I'll admit to not counting it as a point in one's favor.
*I say "he" because all four of our cats are boys.
Saturday, November 15, 2014
What can and will Paul Ryan do over the next two years as Ways and Means chair?
So far as enacting important substantive legislation is concerned, I think the answer is: virtually nothing. This is no reflection on him; rather, it reflects the prevailing political and policy landscape.
So far as enacting legislation with the full expectation of its being vetoed is concerned, that is a matter of his choice and internal Republican legislative politics. I personally see nothing wrong with the Republicans' enacting big bills that they would actually like, but that they know President Obama will veto without serious prospect of override. That can be a legitimate way of framing the Republican side of the 2016 policy debate. But I don't think the Republicans will be able to unite behind responsible tax reform legislation that is genuinely budget-neutral even over the next ten years. This was well shown by the cool reception that Republicans offered Ways and Means Chair Camp's very serious set of business tax reform proposals. While Congressman Ryan would presumably be better situated than Camp to sell such proposals to his own caucus, I doubt that even he could, and also that he would want to.
The really big question is whether Ryan and the Senate Republicans will decide to make major changes in revenue estimating, designed to score tax cut proposals as generally raising revenue, sharply reducing unemployment, etc., even when in fact there is no serious prospect of the proposals actually having the claimed effects. Ryan has been talking this up publicly in aggressive terms. I am willing to credit him with being completely sincere, in the sense of believing that the existing estimating process results in under-measuring the positive effects that he believes enactment of his policy preferences would have. To him, it may therefore seem win-win to push for what is sometimes (on the whole inaccurately) described as more "dynamic" revenue forecasting. Win-win, in the sense that the revenue estimates become both genuinely more accurate and more favorable to his policy views.
But - as the Republicans found in 1994 when they tried to move towards more "dynamic" forecasting - the results they want cannot in fact be yielded by an honest revenue estimating process. And I suspect that leadership figures such as Congressman Ryan, even if they don't currently know this, are about to find out. The conservative or Republican economists who have been named publicly as possible new heads of the Congressional Budget Office are all reputable and honorable people, and they know that an honest, even if "dynamic," revenue estimating process simply can't yield anything close to the numbers that the Republican leadership may not just want, but genuinely believe to be more accurate.
Accordingly, getting the desired numbers, as a regular product of a revised estimating process, would require crossing a Rubicon that at present remains somewhat in the distance. Essentially, it would require dishonestly destroying valuable public institutions that produce information of value to everyone in the process. I am very hopeful that the Republican leadership, once they realize that this is the choice, will recognize that it is neither good policy nor truly in their interest. There is value to a legitimate process, both to provide oneself with better information and to maintain public credibility. And note, of course, that the Democrats may well get back the Senate in 2016, so this really is a two-party game if you look more than two years out into the future.
Again, the Republican leadership in 1995, with Doug Holtz-Eakin playing an important and positive role at the Congressional Budget Office, swiftly came to realize that it made sense to do the right thing (i.e., preserve the legitimacy and honesty of the revenue estimating process). Fingers crossed that it happens again. And while I am not invariably inclined to lean sharply to the most optimistic side when making guesses about the future, I do think there are very good structural and institutional reasons to hope for a positive outcome here.
So far as enacting legislation with the full expectation of its being vetoed is concerned, that is a matter of his choice and internal Republican legislative politics. I personally see nothing wrong with the Republicans' enacting big bills that they would actually like, but that they know President Obama will veto without serious prospect of override. That can be a legitimate way of framing the Republican side of the 2016 policy debate. But I don't think the Republicans will be able to unite behind responsible tax reform legislation that is genuinely budget-neutral even over the next ten years. This was well shown by the cool reception that Republicans offered Ways and Means Chair Camp's very serious set of business tax reform proposals. While Congressman Ryan would presumably be better situated than Camp to sell such proposals to his own caucus, I doubt that even he could, and also that he would want to.
The really big question is whether Ryan and the Senate Republicans will decide to make major changes in revenue estimating, designed to score tax cut proposals as generally raising revenue, sharply reducing unemployment, etc., even when in fact there is no serious prospect of the proposals actually having the claimed effects. Ryan has been talking this up publicly in aggressive terms. I am willing to credit him with being completely sincere, in the sense of believing that the existing estimating process results in under-measuring the positive effects that he believes enactment of his policy preferences would have. To him, it may therefore seem win-win to push for what is sometimes (on the whole inaccurately) described as more "dynamic" revenue forecasting. Win-win, in the sense that the revenue estimates become both genuinely more accurate and more favorable to his policy views.
But - as the Republicans found in 1994 when they tried to move towards more "dynamic" forecasting - the results they want cannot in fact be yielded by an honest revenue estimating process. And I suspect that leadership figures such as Congressman Ryan, even if they don't currently know this, are about to find out. The conservative or Republican economists who have been named publicly as possible new heads of the Congressional Budget Office are all reputable and honorable people, and they know that an honest, even if "dynamic," revenue estimating process simply can't yield anything close to the numbers that the Republican leadership may not just want, but genuinely believe to be more accurate.
Accordingly, getting the desired numbers, as a regular product of a revised estimating process, would require crossing a Rubicon that at present remains somewhat in the distance. Essentially, it would require dishonestly destroying valuable public institutions that produce information of value to everyone in the process. I am very hopeful that the Republican leadership, once they realize that this is the choice, will recognize that it is neither good policy nor truly in their interest. There is value to a legitimate process, both to provide oneself with better information and to maintain public credibility. And note, of course, that the Democrats may well get back the Senate in 2016, so this really is a two-party game if you look more than two years out into the future.
Again, the Republican leadership in 1995, with Doug Holtz-Eakin playing an important and positive role at the Congressional Budget Office, swiftly came to realize that it made sense to do the right thing (i.e., preserve the legitimacy and honesty of the revenue estimating process). Fingers crossed that it happens again. And while I am not invariably inclined to lean sharply to the most optimistic side when making guesses about the future, I do think there are very good structural and institutional reasons to hope for a positive outcome here.
National Tax Association Annual meeting in Santa Fe, part two
Okay, more on the general sessions at this year’s National
Tax Association Annual Meeting. The Day
2 luncheon speaker was Mark Masur, Assistant Secretary of the Treasury for Tax
Policy. He mainly discussed the
prospects for business tax reform in the next Congress. I was struck by how measured and realistic he
was concerning (a) the merits of the reform, which even if net-positive are not
exactly a slam dunk, home run, or whatever sports metaphor denoting a huge
triumph you happen to prefer, and (b) the prospects for enactment of the
reform in the near term, which even a confirmed optimist might rate no higher
than, say, 10 to 15 percent He views the
playout of the current issue in Congress regarding extension of expiring tax
benefits as likely to provide instructive information regarding how the big
players in Congress are likely to be interacting over the next two years. Obviously, finding a mutually acceptable
approach to the expiring tax benefits (including, for example, regarding
whether and how they might be financed) ought to be a great deal easier
politically than working out business tax reform (which I myself view as a
non-starter anyway, unless Congress decides to accept significantly reduced tax
revenues). So if they can’t even do the
easier task without a lot of sturm und drang, the significance will be easy to
discern.
Next up, in terms of general sessions, was a colloquy
concerning three different approaches to business tax reform / taxing capital
income, each considerably more ambitious than just broadening the base (from an
income tax perspective) and cutting the corporate rate. Eric Toder, Alan Auerbach, and Ed Kleinbard
each discussed their particular reform proposals, after which the audience
succeeded in its aim of prodding them to say what they thought was wrong with
each other’s proposals.
Toder, along with Alan Viard, has proposed repealing the
entity-level corporate income tax, which would be replaced with an individual-level
tax on the accrual of gain and loss (without regard to realization) on shares
of publicly traded corporate stock. In
other words, shareholders of publicly traded companies would be taxed on a
mark-to-market basis.
This proposal would clearly solve a lot of problems with the
existing regime. As I attempt to explain
in some length in my books Decoding the U.S. Corporate Tax and Fixing U.S.
International Taxation, once you are taxing corporate income at the entity
level, rather than the owner level, you have guaranteed yourself a number of
very serious problems, made worse in practice by “unforced errors” such as
distinguishing as we do between debt and equity.
The big concern is about its non-application to non-publicly
traded businesses. Suppose, for example,
that this regime had been in place before Facebook went public. Would it still have done so? And how effectively would we be taxing Mark
Zuckerberg if it didn’t? The
pass-through regimes we have under existing law (partnership taxation and subpart
S) have their own set of very serious problems that are not easily mitigated.
Auerbach would replace the existing corporate tax (and the
current rules for taxing non-corporate businesses) with what is essentially a
destination-based VAT, modified to (a) reach all cash flows, financial as well
as real, and (b) allow wages to be deducted, as they are being taxed to
workers. This could easily be part of an
overall X-tax regime, as advocated by David Bradford, and more recently by
Robert Carroll and Alan Viard, in which, once again, we would pretty much solve
most of the problems I analyze in my corporate and international tax
books. Concerns that might be raised
about it include (a) relating it properly to the taxation of individuals, if
not accompanied by the enactment of a broader X-tax, and (b) whether its
treatment of financial flows, which are deductible / includable or not
depending on whether or not they in effect cross the U.S. border, would invite
abusive gaming that was hard rather than easy to address.
Kleinbard has proposed a business enterprise income tax
(BEIT) in lieu of current rules for both corporate and non-corporate
businesses. Businesses would get
interest on basis via a cost of capital allowance (COCA). This resembles proposals (just for
corporations) to address the distinction between debt and equity by providing
an allowance for corporate equity (ACE) – in effect, an imputed interest
deduction on equity to match the actual interest deduction for corporate debt –
except that Kleinbard would use the COCA in lieu of actual interest deductions,
an important distinction from ACE proposals given that financial instruments
denominated debt can be used to pay out a lot more than just the normal
risk-free rate of return. The proposal
would in effect make the entity-level tax a consumption tax, since interest on
basis is present value equivalent to expensing, but rents and owner-employees’
undistributed labor income would face the entity level tax. At the individual level, Kleinbard would
impute a taxable return to holding debt, stock, etcetera, but the income being
imputed here would exceed the COCA deductions being claimed at the entity level,
if the basis of these financial assets exceeded the basis of business assets at
the entity level. This might often be
the case, due, e.g., to owner-level sales of stock that had appreciated at
faster than the normal rate of return, along with cost recovery deductions
being taken at the entity level.
The BEIT as envisioned by Kleinbard would also involve
worldwide taxation for all U.S. companies, at the full domestic rate and
without the deferral that present law generally provides for amounts earned
through foreign subsidiaries. In other
words, full global consolidation. He
would allow a foreign tax credit, which I of course don’t like (I’ve argued
extensively elsewhere in favor of lowering the US tax rate on foreign source
income in lieu of providing foreign tax credits).
One of the main challenges one could raise to Kleinbard’s
proposal is that taxing U.S. companies on a current basis on their foreign
extra-normal returns (i.e., those in excess of the COCA deduction), at the full domestic rate albeit with foreign tax credits, would
be problematic in a world that has lots of countries with territorial systems
for taxing multinationals (although it is true that some of these countries use
residence-based rules to address income-shifting to tax havens). He argues that meaningful corporate
residence rules, based on such factors as where the managers are rather than
just where the company at the top of the chain is incorporated, would make it
extremely hard for existing U.S. companies to expatriate. The current inversion problem reflects that
our corporate residence rules are so formalistic and porous. But even if existing U.S. companies can’t readily
expatriate under a BEIT with much tougher corporate residence rules - which is very plausible - there are serious issues about the long-term sustainability and impact of a
global regime for U.S. businesses if other countries are doing it very
differently.
One point of general agreement was that all three proposals might offer enormous improvement over current law if they could actually be enacted without being wrecked by political considerations. But none seems likely to be imminent, which of course is no argument against making sure that people hear about them.
One point of general agreement was that all three proposals might offer enormous improvement over current law if they could actually be enacted without being wrecked by political considerations. But none seems likely to be imminent, which of course is no argument against making sure that people hear about them.
The last general session at this year’s NTA Annual Meeting
honored Jim Poterba, this year’s Holland Award winner for lifetime
contributions to the field of public finance.
Even leaving aside Jim’s outstanding academic work over decades, which
by itself amply supported the prize, the session permitted dozens of leading
public finance economists around the country, to whom he has been a tremendous
mentor and inspiration, to express their gratitude. Jim proves the proposition that sometimes
virtue and merit are duly rewarded.
Once I'm back in NYC, I will post here the slides for my talk on my behavioral economics / retirement saving paper, Multiple Myopias, Multiple Selves, and the Under-Saving Problem. I will also probably post my comments on a very nice paper for which I was the discussant, presented there by USC economist Mark Philips. I had planned to simply post here remarks that I had written out in advance. But as I was thinking about my remarks at the actual session, which I had time to do as Mark went third, I decided I wasn't entirely happy with what I had in hand, and spoke extemporaneously instead. If I get a chance to write that up briefly, I will do so and post it.
National Tax Association Annual Meeting in Santa Fe, part one
Today will be the third and last day of the National Tax
Association’s 107th Annual Meeting, being held in Santa Fe. It’s been nice to see lots of old friends
here, from economics, law, and accounting.
Obviously economists are the largest group, but the law contingent is
significant these days, and a bunch of junior people appear to be making it a
regular thing, which is great both for them and the NTA. There is some tendency for the economists and
lawyers to do things separately, but there is also a fair amount of
interaction, and in any event the optimal mixing percentage is less than 100
percent given distinct professional interests and styles.
Next year’s NTA Annual Meeting will be held in Boston, which
is certainly easier to get to for many of us than Santa Fe, and the program
chairs will be Matthew Weinzierl of the Harvard Business School and Dhammika
Dharmapala of the University of Chicago Law School.
With lots of good panels in each time slot, one had to miss
a lot of good things. (I also ended up
missing the Georgia O’Keefe Museum, even though it’s right next door.) But there were four general sessions, each
meriting a brief mention here.
The first day’s lunch speaker was Joe Stiglitz. He argues that, with proper use of Pigovian
taxes such as a carbon tax, along with Henry George land or site value taxes,
the U.S. government can raise more than enough revenue over the long run
without doing serious economic harm. He
also pointedly dissented from academic uses of the 1976 Atkinson-Stiglitz
theorem regarding equal commodity taxation to draw pro-consumption tax,
anti-income tax, conclusions. But when
asked what would be wrong with using a progressive consumption tax plus
inheritance/gift tax, in lieu of a capital income tax that may have a hard time
getting away from realization problems, his answer appeared to focus mainly on
rents, which would in principle generally be reached under a progressive consumption
tax and also, to the extent not spent during their lifetimes by those earning
the rents, by the inheritance/gift tax.
Stiglitz criticized Thomas Piketty’s economic analysis (as
distinct from statistical analysis) in Capital in the Twenty-First Century on the
ground that Piketty has confused “capital,” in the sense of productive inputs,
with “wealth,” in the sense of the market value of existing resources. To illustrate (using his example), suppose
that in France there is a huge run-up in the value of real estate – reflecting,
say, the global popularity of Paris and the French Riviera as attractive
destinations. This increases the wealth
held by people in France (ignoring the issue of French versus overseas
ownership of French land). But it does
nothing to increase the capital that can be deployed in economic production. So while the landowners would presumably now
be earning r (the normal return) on a higher valuation, they would not have
increased productive resources in the economy, hence there would be no tendency
for the increased wealth – unlike increased capital being deployed productively
– to bid down r.
Perhaps this is enough for one post, so I will add a second one
on the other general sessions at this year’s NTA.
Saturday, November 08, 2014
Life with Pandora
I've been using elliptical machines in the health club for at least 15 years now - vital, as you move on in life, not just to maintain conditioning but also, I think, to slow down aging - and I can only tolerate it if listening to music. At first I'd take CDs and hope the battery didn't run out mid-session. Then I switched to the iPhone and playlists. Being a member of the Album Generation, I tended to want to have whole albums (actual or constructed by me). But you can only fit so many on your phone, and even if you keep dozens of favorites available, often on a given day you don't want to hear any of them. Plus it's a nuisance to have to keep on adding and deleting playlists. So recently I switched to Pandora.
Generally it does the job, especially as one can skip ahead when needed. The ads are annoying (I haven't upgraded to ad-free), but this just means taking off my headphones, and holding them in my hands for 30 second stretches, twice in the course of a 35 minute workout session.
Somehow I wish the algorithm could be more insightful, regarding not just my overall tastes, but even my mood on a given day. But then again, a world in which it could read my mood might on the whole be a bit dystopian.
The variety of selections that you get in rapid succession can be fun. Today I decided to keep track of the playlist it gave me, which went like this:
XTC, Hendrix, Belle and Sebastian, Fiona Apple, Arthur Alexander, Led Zeppelin (not one of my picked artists, and I pushed "next" after about 2 minutes), Pavement, Dylan, Queen (also not one of mine, and this lasted less than a minute), Sex Pistols, Kinks, Shins, Velvet Underground, Rancid (also not one of mine), Buddy Holly.
UPDATE: At the suggestion of a reader of this blog, I've now added Spotify to my repertoire, and have tailored it to have generally different coverage for me than does Pandora.
Generally it does the job, especially as one can skip ahead when needed. The ads are annoying (I haven't upgraded to ad-free), but this just means taking off my headphones, and holding them in my hands for 30 second stretches, twice in the course of a 35 minute workout session.
Somehow I wish the algorithm could be more insightful, regarding not just my overall tastes, but even my mood on a given day. But then again, a world in which it could read my mood might on the whole be a bit dystopian.
The variety of selections that you get in rapid succession can be fun. Today I decided to keep track of the playlist it gave me, which went like this:
XTC, Hendrix, Belle and Sebastian, Fiona Apple, Arthur Alexander, Led Zeppelin (not one of my picked artists, and I pushed "next" after about 2 minutes), Pavement, Dylan, Queen (also not one of mine, and this lasted less than a minute), Sex Pistols, Kinks, Shins, Velvet Underground, Rancid (also not one of mine), Buddy Holly.
UPDATE: At the suggestion of a reader of this blog, I've now added Spotify to my repertoire, and have tailored it to have generally different coverage for me than does Pandora.
Friday, November 07, 2014
More upcoming talks
I seem to have scheduled a fairly busy sabbatical semester for myself.
Next week I'm going to the National Tax Association Annual Meeting in Santa Fe. For the first and only time, I'll be giving a talk on another of my currently-in-press articles, Multiple Myopia, Multiple Selves, and the Under-Saving Problem. This piece, forthcoming as the anchor article in an issue of the Connecticut Law Review article that will also feature several responses by other people, discusses the behavioral economics literature in relation to income tax "incentives" for retirement, nudges and their implications for the income tax vs. consumption tax debate, Social Security design, etc. It's far less an advocacy piece than a "look how little we know" piece. I will post my slides for the talk here after the session.
(My other two articles currently in press are the Piketty paper, forthcoming in the Tax Law Review, and the short corporate tax reform paper that I gave in Boston recently. You can see slides for the latter piece here, and it will be appearing in Tax Notes sometime this December, but I won't be posting it on SSRN until then.)
While at NTA, I'll also be the commentator on an interesting tax incidence article by USC economists Richard Green and Mark Philips. My comments will just be short - the slot I have is just 5 minutes - but I'll probably post them here as well afterwards.
The following week, I'll be giving another talk on the Piketty paper, this time at USC Law School.
Then I suppose that's it for the year, non-business travel aside.
In January (words that I dread typing, because it makes me think about polar vortices), I will be co-teaching the NYU Tax Policy Colloquium for the 20th (!) time. My economist colleague will be Alan Viard, whom I look forward to working with for the first time, The schedule isn't yet up on the NYU webpage, but you can see the dates and speakers (although not as yet the paper titles) here. The sessions will be on Tuesdays from 4-6 pm, from late January through early May. The overall balance will be more towards lawyers and legal topics, and less towards economists and true econ papers, than was the case last year - reflecting my sense that, from a proper institutional standpoint, we tilted a hair too much the other way last time around.
Next week I'm going to the National Tax Association Annual Meeting in Santa Fe. For the first and only time, I'll be giving a talk on another of my currently-in-press articles, Multiple Myopia, Multiple Selves, and the Under-Saving Problem. This piece, forthcoming as the anchor article in an issue of the Connecticut Law Review article that will also feature several responses by other people, discusses the behavioral economics literature in relation to income tax "incentives" for retirement, nudges and their implications for the income tax vs. consumption tax debate, Social Security design, etc. It's far less an advocacy piece than a "look how little we know" piece. I will post my slides for the talk here after the session.
(My other two articles currently in press are the Piketty paper, forthcoming in the Tax Law Review, and the short corporate tax reform paper that I gave in Boston recently. You can see slides for the latter piece here, and it will be appearing in Tax Notes sometime this December, but I won't be posting it on SSRN until then.)
While at NTA, I'll also be the commentator on an interesting tax incidence article by USC economists Richard Green and Mark Philips. My comments will just be short - the slot I have is just 5 minutes - but I'll probably post them here as well afterwards.
The following week, I'll be giving another talk on the Piketty paper, this time at USC Law School.
Then I suppose that's it for the year, non-business travel aside.
In January (words that I dread typing, because it makes me think about polar vortices), I will be co-teaching the NYU Tax Policy Colloquium for the 20th (!) time. My economist colleague will be Alan Viard, whom I look forward to working with for the first time, The schedule isn't yet up on the NYU webpage, but you can see the dates and speakers (although not as yet the paper titles) here. The sessions will be on Tuesdays from 4-6 pm, from late January through early May. The overall balance will be more towards lawyers and legal topics, and less towards economists and true econ papers, than was the case last year - reflecting my sense that, from a proper institutional standpoint, we tilted a hair too much the other way last time around.
Monday, November 03, 2014
Article on Piketty's Capital in the Twenty-First Century posted on SSRN
Joe Bankman and I have no posted our article on the Piketty book on SSRN. Its title is "Piketty in America: A Tale of Two Literatures," and you can find it available for download here.
Friday, October 31, 2014
NYU event on Kleinbard book
Yesterday Ed Kleinbard presented his new book at an early evening session at NYU Law School. Linda Sugin and I then offered comments. Unfortunately, perhaps, for the intellectual diversity of the event, we both approached it more from the left, leaving viewpoints more from the right under-represented there.
My remarks went something like this:
My remarks went something like this:
The book is
great, a tour de force and an important contribution to public debate. I agree with the great majority of it. But since that’s no fun to discuss, I’ll
emphasize my main disagreement, which relates to high-end inequality, or the
recent lift-off from everyone else of not of the top one percent, but rather
the top one-tenth of a percent (which is where a recent paper by Emmanuel Saez
and Gabriel Zucman finds that U.S. wealth gains since 1979 have been almost
entirely concentrated).
I consider rising
high-end inequality, in the top one-tenth of one percent, more important and
broadly problematic than Ed does. Now, this
is at least partly an empirical question – what adverse effects, if any, does
it actually have on everyone else? – but that is hard to evaluate. So, while both Ed and I are open to evidence,
we may have to continue to disagree about the importance of this issue, at
least for the time being.
Because of this
difference, at least in emphasis, I attach more importance than Ed does to
distinguishing, both conceptually and empirically, between high-end and low-end
inequality. A measure like the Gini
coefficient fails to do this, and not because of its particular tradeoffs or flaws,
but because it’s a single overall measure.
When Ed says that even taxes that are regressive in isolation can create
greater equality if they are spent right, he is emphasizing the effect on
low-end inequality. You can’t do much
about high-end inequality, at least directly or in the short run, through
greater social spending.
Given the greater
importance that I ascribe to high-end inequality, I am more eager than Ed is to
address it through the fiscal system, which really does mean the tax
system. Now, there may be important
non-fiscal tools for addressing it – for example, regulations concerning
intellectual property, the financial sector, corporate governance, and campaign
financing. But if we want to seriously
address high-end inequality through the fiscal system, it has to be done
through higher taxes at the top.
Now, this doesn’t
necessarily have to mean higher graduated rates in the income tax, although it could. Estate or inheritance taxes with fewer
planning outs might play a big role as well, as might income tax reforms such
as taxing asset appreciation at death, and perhaps finding a way to tax
borrowing against appreciated property, so the likes of Larry Ellison can’t
avoid tax on high current consumption. (Ed
says, by the way, that he supports the use of estate taxes to address dynastic
wealth transfers – but he doesn’t emphasize it much, nor does he fully explain
why it might be exempt from the political logic that he offers for steering
away from greater high-end rate graduation.)
Although there
are lots of different ways to skin the apple, I am more open than Ed is to
having high income tax rates at the top, as Diamond and Saez have
suggested. By the way, they stop at 73
percent, including state and local taxes, under a low estimate of elasticity,
because they are just trying to revenue-maximize at the top. There’s an argument for going beyond that if
you believe that high-end wealth concentration has net negative externalities,
like pollution.
Raising the
Social Security earnings cap would be a significant (12.4 percent) tax rate
increase on people who are well above the median – but obviously it starts
applying long before we reach the top tenth of a percent. So, while that would be a progressive tax
change, it wouldn’t be aimed where my special concerns lie regarding what’s
happened since 1979.
Of course, there
is more than I’ve acknowledged so far to Ed’s side of the argument against
specially aiming higher up. So let’s
back up for a minute.
This is at least
three books in one – perhaps more. But
it certainly includes at least the following three:
First,
it’s a book about substantive policy analysis.
What are the issues, and what are the tools that we might use to address
them? A core argument is that, in
addressing inequality through the fiscal system, we should focus on spending,
not tax progressivity. Again, while I
agree with this, it addresses low-end inequality, to the relative exclusion of
high-end inequality, and I would like to address both, while using Ed’s
approach for the low end.
Second,
it’s a book about morals and rhetoric.
The two are linked because appealing to people’s underlying moral
beliefs is crucial to rhetorical success.
Here Ed does a great job of attacking market triumphalism.
But I wonder if he
is being either too optimistic about moral argument’s capacity to cajole people
into caring more about the bottom end, or else too pessimistic about its doing the
same at the top end. In any event, I wonder
about the substantial gap between his optimism and pessimism on these two
scores. And while he views addressing low-end
inequality and high-end inequality as substitutes – in his view, pursuing one
would undermine pursuing the other – it’s also possible that they could
function as complements.
Third,
this is a book about political economy. Ed
believes that some approaches to addressing inequality might succeed, while others
will surely fail. Here I’d make the same
point about whether addressing high-end and low-end inequality have (a) such
different prospects and (b) are necessarily substitutes rather than
complements.
Okay, more about
the first book, concerning substantive policy analysis. Ed notes that recent increases in inequality
have been driven by the rise of the top 1 percent.
In support of his
nonetheless focusing almost exclusively on low-end inequality, the case for
addressing it admittedly is much more clear-cut than that for addressing
high-end inequality. When we think about
helping the poor, the idea is to make them better off. That’s not hard to endorse. But when we think about addressing extreme
high-end inequality, is the idea just to make those people worse off? Why would we want to do that?
The answer is
that there are reasons for thinking that extreme high-end inequality may indeed
be bad for everyone else. It’s not just
a matter of the declining marginal utility of consumption, which merely
suggests that others would get more utility out of a dollar than people at the
top do. Extreme high-end wealth
inequality can potentially have directly adverse effects on the bottom 99.9
percent.
But let’s start
with declining marginal utility, since Ed disparages it as a ground for wanting
to level down as well as up. In the book, he notes that his former clients
loved money so much that the theory of declining marginal utility seemed not to
apply to them. But I have two responses.
First, that
example does not concern the marginal utility of consumption, but rather of the
income and wealth amounts that they get to see reported on pieces of paper. Neither Ed’s super-rich former clients nor
their heirs are likely to spend all of that money any time soon. So a large part of what they love is the
abstraction – gross dollar numbers that they see reported to them.
Among the key
elements of this may be keeping score against their peers. But if you tax all of them at the same high
rate, their relative ranks stay the same.
And if what they like is the power and status that it brings them relative
to everyone below, that is a mainly zero sum phenomenon. More power and status for them means less for
others.
I also question
the admittedly standard practice in welfare economics of taking preferences as
given. I would argue that some
combinations of people’s preferences can lead to higher total utility than
other combinations. Suppose one person
enjoys hurting or oppressing others. The
standard utilitarian answer to why we shouldn’t let this happen is that surely
the victims’ pain is greater than the inflictor’s pleasure. But what if it isn’t?
Well, probably it
is. But even if it isn’t, it seems
obvious that we could get to a greater overall welfare level if the oppressor’s
utility function instead had inputs that were at least neutral regarding
whether others were suffering. And
preferences may be socially malleable over time, even if not for a given
individual whose ways are set.
It makes sense
for us to think about the long run, not just feelings that are based on expectations
today. Say I’m a hedge fund manager who
believes that making me pay tax on my labor income at ordinary income rates,
rather than capital gains rates, is on a par with Kristallnacht. A billionaire actually said something like
that recently. And while his comment
could not easily have been more ludicrous and offensive than it was, it
certainly testified to his genuinely strong feelings. Does that mean his marginal disutility of
paying the same tax rate as the rest of us is really, really strong? To me, even if so, that means he has
preferences that shouldn’t be encouraged, and that over time, with habituation
to a better system, could change.
In sum, I think
that focusing on the marginal utility of consumption has more juice than Ed
attributes to it, insofar as justifying a response to high-end inequality is
concerned. But it’s only a small part of
the argument for concern about the takeoff in recent decades by the top tenth
of a percent. Other important points include
the following:
--First, the fact
that high-end inequality makes other people feel worse than they would in a
more equal society. There is extensive
behavioral research evidence confirming this.
People say they’d prefer to have somewhat less in a more equal society, rather
than somewhat more in a society where they are far below everyone else. Utility comes not just from own consumption,
but relative consumption. This reflects that
we are a competitive social animal.
--Second, political
economy. I see lots of evidence that a
shift towards plutocracy is choking our political system’s capacity to respond
to most people’s interests and concerns.
Consider the work of Princeton political scientist Martin Gilens,
showing that policy preferences below the very top appear to have almost no
influence on policy outcomes.
Case in point, I
think it’s in good part because of rising plutocracy that there has been so
little interest among policymaking elites in stimulating demand to address high
unemployment still lingering from the Great Recession. You might have to challenge the concentration
of power at the very top in order to make the government more responsive to other
people’s interests.
Now, campaign
finance law might be part of the response, if there weren’t 5 Supreme Court
justices asserting that the right to give a billion dollars to a candidate is
sacred, while it’s perfectly fine to disenfranchise millions of voters through
the equivalent of poll taxes. But even if
the Supreme Court majority actually respected our country’s best traditions,
rather than being eager to trample on them, campaign finance reform might not
be enough. When things are so unequal, the
power imbalance is going to seep through one way or another. So you may actually have to address high-end
inequality in order to preserve meaningful democracy.
--Third, social
solidarity. The reason you have all
these billionaires complaining about Kristallnacht, the moment anyone even
looks at them funny, is that such radical inequality as we have today undermines
the sense of shared membership and enterprise that you may need for a
successful democratic society. These
people end up living lives completely separated from the rest of us, and they
grow accustomed to receiving enormous deference most of the time. They start to find democratic politics and
manners unacceptable, and they get paranoid that the voters will take it all
away. I don’t entirely blame so many of
the super-rich for feeling this way, even though they appear to have immense
political power, with fealty from the leaders of both major parties. It goes with the territory to feel paranoia. But the fact that they feel so threatened reflects
the destruction of cohesion and social capital.
Let me turn
briefly now to Ed’s second and third books – the ones on morals and rhetoric,
and on political economy.
On morals and
rhetoric, Ed believes that progressives need to focus more on the old-fashioned
virtues, including basic human decency, and on saying “social insurance” rather
than “redistribution.” I agree about those
rhetorical choices.
But I am not so sure
that “we are better than this.” For
example, our country’s racial history makes it difficult to motivate helping
people at the bottom. Ed appeals to
altruism, and to the appeal of being a mensch, not a jerk. But altruism often takes the form of loyalty
to one’s own racial, ethnic, or other social group, with an accompanying lack
of compassion for, or even hatred of, other groups.
Politics is also
importantly driven by economic interests.
And it’s not clear why those who are in the driver’s seat would share
Ed’s concern about low-end inequality, even if high-end inequality is allowed
to stand unchecked.
Jared Bernstein,
in a review of Ed’s book that was extremely favorable, nonetheless made the
following comment, based on the book’s title, “We Are Better Than This”:
“Just who is this ‘We’ he keeps talking about? More
than any time in our recent history, we are balkanized by income, class,
ideology, religion, politics, race, and pretty much every other dimension you
can think of. And if there is no coherent ‘we’ then there can be no clear path
for ‘us’ to take together that will make us ‘better than this.’"
One of the book’s
important themes is combating market triumphalism. But discrediting it could motivate addressing
inequality at the top, as well as the bottom.
If the market’s losers don’t deserve contempt for having lost, then perhaps
the winners don’t deserve quite so much genuflection for having won. And if you can’t counteract the moral influence of market triumphalism, then
addressing inequality at both ends is
difficult. The two might be tightly
linked.
Finally, let’s
turn to the political economy book. Ed
makes a number of judgments that are contestable – which is not to say wrong. Opposing judgments would also be contestable, as this is a murky area. To give an example, Ed argues that, if you
advocate highly graduated income tax rates, you get into a class war, zero-sum
framework where you inevitably lose. An
opposing view would be that you need to weaken the grip of plutocracy at the
top before you can achieve anything at the bottom. I find it hard to tell who’s right.
Plus, there’s the
question of why some increases in high-end taxes (such as from base-broadening
or making the estate tax more effective) won’t generate the same political
backfire as raising high-end rates. Ed
may have specific distinctions in mind, but it’s bound to be debatable.
Insofar as the aim
is to avoid angering the rich, the book employs what I call the “Mongo” theory,
derived from the movie Blazing Saddles. Mongo is the gigantic brute who can punch out
a horse, and who initially is working for the bad guys. Gene Wilder tells the good guy sheriff,
played by Cleavon Little, “Don’t shoot Mongo – it only makes him angry.” Likewise here, Ed fears that if you use steeply
progressive rates to go after the super-rich, they will oppose the rest of your
agenda. But what if they’ll oppose it
anyway?
In the movie, the
sheriff tricks Mongo with an exploding Candygram, and Mongo then changes
sides. I’m not sure how we can exploit
that insight here. But leaving the very top
alone may do less to placate the opposition, than to leave hostile forces still
in control of our political and economic system.
In sum, I agree with
Ed that addressing low-end inequality depends much more on revenue adequacy and
spending levels than on tax rate progressivity at the top. But there are distinct reasons for addressing
inequality at the top, not just the bottom.
And, as a matter of morals, rhetoric, and political economy, it is hard
to be sure whether addressing the two kinds of inequality is more a case of
substitution – you can only do one, at most, as Ed believes – or of
complementarity, where they are best seen as parts of the same enterprise.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)