My remarks went something like this:
The book is
great, a tour de force and an important contribution to public debate. I agree with the great majority of it. But since that’s no fun to discuss, I’ll
emphasize my main disagreement, which relates to high-end inequality, or the
recent lift-off from everyone else of not of the top one percent, but rather
the top one-tenth of a percent (which is where a recent paper by Emmanuel Saez
and Gabriel Zucman finds that U.S. wealth gains since 1979 have been almost
entirely concentrated).
I consider rising
high-end inequality, in the top one-tenth of one percent, more important and
broadly problematic than Ed does. Now, this
is at least partly an empirical question – what adverse effects, if any, does
it actually have on everyone else? – but that is hard to evaluate. So, while both Ed and I are open to evidence,
we may have to continue to disagree about the importance of this issue, at
least for the time being.
Because of this
difference, at least in emphasis, I attach more importance than Ed does to
distinguishing, both conceptually and empirically, between high-end and low-end
inequality. A measure like the Gini
coefficient fails to do this, and not because of its particular tradeoffs or flaws,
but because it’s a single overall measure.
When Ed says that even taxes that are regressive in isolation can create
greater equality if they are spent right, he is emphasizing the effect on
low-end inequality. You can’t do much
about high-end inequality, at least directly or in the short run, through
greater social spending.
Given the greater
importance that I ascribe to high-end inequality, I am more eager than Ed is to
address it through the fiscal system, which really does mean the tax
system. Now, there may be important
non-fiscal tools for addressing it – for example, regulations concerning
intellectual property, the financial sector, corporate governance, and campaign
financing. But if we want to seriously
address high-end inequality through the fiscal system, it has to be done
through higher taxes at the top.
Now, this doesn’t
necessarily have to mean higher graduated rates in the income tax, although it could. Estate or inheritance taxes with fewer
planning outs might play a big role as well, as might income tax reforms such
as taxing asset appreciation at death, and perhaps finding a way to tax
borrowing against appreciated property, so the likes of Larry Ellison can’t
avoid tax on high current consumption. (Ed
says, by the way, that he supports the use of estate taxes to address dynastic
wealth transfers – but he doesn’t emphasize it much, nor does he fully explain
why it might be exempt from the political logic that he offers for steering
away from greater high-end rate graduation.)
Although there
are lots of different ways to skin the apple, I am more open than Ed is to
having high income tax rates at the top, as Diamond and Saez have
suggested. By the way, they stop at 73
percent, including state and local taxes, under a low estimate of elasticity,
because they are just trying to revenue-maximize at the top. There’s an argument for going beyond that if
you believe that high-end wealth concentration has net negative externalities,
like pollution.
Raising the
Social Security earnings cap would be a significant (12.4 percent) tax rate
increase on people who are well above the median – but obviously it starts
applying long before we reach the top tenth of a percent. So, while that would be a progressive tax
change, it wouldn’t be aimed where my special concerns lie regarding what’s
happened since 1979.
Of course, there
is more than I’ve acknowledged so far to Ed’s side of the argument against
specially aiming higher up. So let’s
back up for a minute.
This is at least
three books in one – perhaps more. But
it certainly includes at least the following three:
First,
it’s a book about substantive policy analysis.
What are the issues, and what are the tools that we might use to address
them? A core argument is that, in
addressing inequality through the fiscal system, we should focus on spending,
not tax progressivity. Again, while I
agree with this, it addresses low-end inequality, to the relative exclusion of
high-end inequality, and I would like to address both, while using Ed’s
approach for the low end.
Second,
it’s a book about morals and rhetoric.
The two are linked because appealing to people’s underlying moral
beliefs is crucial to rhetorical success.
Here Ed does a great job of attacking market triumphalism.
But I wonder if he
is being either too optimistic about moral argument’s capacity to cajole people
into caring more about the bottom end, or else too pessimistic about its doing the
same at the top end. In any event, I wonder
about the substantial gap between his optimism and pessimism on these two
scores. And while he views addressing low-end
inequality and high-end inequality as substitutes – in his view, pursuing one
would undermine pursuing the other – it’s also possible that they could
function as complements.
Third,
this is a book about political economy. Ed
believes that some approaches to addressing inequality might succeed, while others
will surely fail. Here I’d make the same
point about whether addressing high-end and low-end inequality have (a) such
different prospects and (b) are necessarily substitutes rather than
complements.
Okay, more about
the first book, concerning substantive policy analysis. Ed notes that recent increases in inequality
have been driven by the rise of the top 1 percent.
In support of his
nonetheless focusing almost exclusively on low-end inequality, the case for
addressing it admittedly is much more clear-cut than that for addressing
high-end inequality. When we think about
helping the poor, the idea is to make them better off. That’s not hard to endorse. But when we think about addressing extreme
high-end inequality, is the idea just to make those people worse off? Why would we want to do that?
The answer is
that there are reasons for thinking that extreme high-end inequality may indeed
be bad for everyone else. It’s not just
a matter of the declining marginal utility of consumption, which merely
suggests that others would get more utility out of a dollar than people at the
top do. Extreme high-end wealth
inequality can potentially have directly adverse effects on the bottom 99.9
percent.
But let’s start
with declining marginal utility, since Ed disparages it as a ground for wanting
to level down as well as up. In the book, he notes that his former clients
loved money so much that the theory of declining marginal utility seemed not to
apply to them. But I have two responses.
First, that
example does not concern the marginal utility of consumption, but rather of the
income and wealth amounts that they get to see reported on pieces of paper. Neither Ed’s super-rich former clients nor
their heirs are likely to spend all of that money any time soon. So a large part of what they love is the
abstraction – gross dollar numbers that they see reported to them.
Among the key
elements of this may be keeping score against their peers. But if you tax all of them at the same high
rate, their relative ranks stay the same.
And if what they like is the power and status that it brings them relative
to everyone below, that is a mainly zero sum phenomenon. More power and status for them means less for
others.
I also question
the admittedly standard practice in welfare economics of taking preferences as
given. I would argue that some
combinations of people’s preferences can lead to higher total utility than
other combinations. Suppose one person
enjoys hurting or oppressing others. The
standard utilitarian answer to why we shouldn’t let this happen is that surely
the victims’ pain is greater than the inflictor’s pleasure. But what if it isn’t?
Well, probably it
is. But even if it isn’t, it seems
obvious that we could get to a greater overall welfare level if the oppressor’s
utility function instead had inputs that were at least neutral regarding
whether others were suffering. And
preferences may be socially malleable over time, even if not for a given
individual whose ways are set.
It makes sense
for us to think about the long run, not just feelings that are based on expectations
today. Say I’m a hedge fund manager who
believes that making me pay tax on my labor income at ordinary income rates,
rather than capital gains rates, is on a par with Kristallnacht. A billionaire actually said something like
that recently. And while his comment
could not easily have been more ludicrous and offensive than it was, it
certainly testified to his genuinely strong feelings. Does that mean his marginal disutility of
paying the same tax rate as the rest of us is really, really strong? To me, even if so, that means he has
preferences that shouldn’t be encouraged, and that over time, with habituation
to a better system, could change.
In sum, I think
that focusing on the marginal utility of consumption has more juice than Ed
attributes to it, insofar as justifying a response to high-end inequality is
concerned. But it’s only a small part of
the argument for concern about the takeoff in recent decades by the top tenth
of a percent. Other important points include
the following:
--First, the fact
that high-end inequality makes other people feel worse than they would in a
more equal society. There is extensive
behavioral research evidence confirming this.
People say they’d prefer to have somewhat less in a more equal society, rather
than somewhat more in a society where they are far below everyone else. Utility comes not just from own consumption,
but relative consumption. This reflects that
we are a competitive social animal.
--Second, political
economy. I see lots of evidence that a
shift towards plutocracy is choking our political system’s capacity to respond
to most people’s interests and concerns.
Consider the work of Princeton political scientist Martin Gilens,
showing that policy preferences below the very top appear to have almost no
influence on policy outcomes.
Case in point, I
think it’s in good part because of rising plutocracy that there has been so
little interest among policymaking elites in stimulating demand to address high
unemployment still lingering from the Great Recession. You might have to challenge the concentration
of power at the very top in order to make the government more responsive to other
people’s interests.
Now, campaign
finance law might be part of the response, if there weren’t 5 Supreme Court
justices asserting that the right to give a billion dollars to a candidate is
sacred, while it’s perfectly fine to disenfranchise millions of voters through
the equivalent of poll taxes. But even if
the Supreme Court majority actually respected our country’s best traditions,
rather than being eager to trample on them, campaign finance reform might not
be enough. When things are so unequal, the
power imbalance is going to seep through one way or another. So you may actually have to address high-end
inequality in order to preserve meaningful democracy.
--Third, social
solidarity. The reason you have all
these billionaires complaining about Kristallnacht, the moment anyone even
looks at them funny, is that such radical inequality as we have today undermines
the sense of shared membership and enterprise that you may need for a
successful democratic society. These
people end up living lives completely separated from the rest of us, and they
grow accustomed to receiving enormous deference most of the time. They start to find democratic politics and
manners unacceptable, and they get paranoid that the voters will take it all
away. I don’t entirely blame so many of
the super-rich for feeling this way, even though they appear to have immense
political power, with fealty from the leaders of both major parties. It goes with the territory to feel paranoia. But the fact that they feel so threatened reflects
the destruction of cohesion and social capital.
Let me turn
briefly now to Ed’s second and third books – the ones on morals and rhetoric,
and on political economy.
On morals and
rhetoric, Ed believes that progressives need to focus more on the old-fashioned
virtues, including basic human decency, and on saying “social insurance” rather
than “redistribution.” I agree about those
rhetorical choices.
But I am not so sure
that “we are better than this.” For
example, our country’s racial history makes it difficult to motivate helping
people at the bottom. Ed appeals to
altruism, and to the appeal of being a mensch, not a jerk. But altruism often takes the form of loyalty
to one’s own racial, ethnic, or other social group, with an accompanying lack
of compassion for, or even hatred of, other groups.
Politics is also
importantly driven by economic interests.
And it’s not clear why those who are in the driver’s seat would share
Ed’s concern about low-end inequality, even if high-end inequality is allowed
to stand unchecked.
Jared Bernstein,
in a review of Ed’s book that was extremely favorable, nonetheless made the
following comment, based on the book’s title, “We Are Better Than This”:
“Just who is this ‘We’ he keeps talking about? More
than any time in our recent history, we are balkanized by income, class,
ideology, religion, politics, race, and pretty much every other dimension you
can think of. And if there is no coherent ‘we’ then there can be no clear path
for ‘us’ to take together that will make us ‘better than this.’"
One of the book’s
important themes is combating market triumphalism. But discrediting it could motivate addressing
inequality at the top, as well as the bottom.
If the market’s losers don’t deserve contempt for having lost, then perhaps
the winners don’t deserve quite so much genuflection for having won. And if you can’t counteract the moral influence of market triumphalism, then
addressing inequality at both ends is
difficult. The two might be tightly
linked.
Finally, let’s
turn to the political economy book. Ed
makes a number of judgments that are contestable – which is not to say wrong. Opposing judgments would also be contestable, as this is a murky area. To give an example, Ed argues that, if you
advocate highly graduated income tax rates, you get into a class war, zero-sum
framework where you inevitably lose. An
opposing view would be that you need to weaken the grip of plutocracy at the
top before you can achieve anything at the bottom. I find it hard to tell who’s right.
Plus, there’s the
question of why some increases in high-end taxes (such as from base-broadening
or making the estate tax more effective) won’t generate the same political
backfire as raising high-end rates. Ed
may have specific distinctions in mind, but it’s bound to be debatable.
Insofar as the aim
is to avoid angering the rich, the book employs what I call the “Mongo” theory,
derived from the movie Blazing Saddles. Mongo is the gigantic brute who can punch out
a horse, and who initially is working for the bad guys. Gene Wilder tells the good guy sheriff,
played by Cleavon Little, “Don’t shoot Mongo – it only makes him angry.” Likewise here, Ed fears that if you use steeply
progressive rates to go after the super-rich, they will oppose the rest of your
agenda. But what if they’ll oppose it
anyway?
In the movie, the
sheriff tricks Mongo with an exploding Candygram, and Mongo then changes
sides. I’m not sure how we can exploit
that insight here. But leaving the very top
alone may do less to placate the opposition, than to leave hostile forces still
in control of our political and economic system.
In sum, I agree with
Ed that addressing low-end inequality depends much more on revenue adequacy and
spending levels than on tax rate progressivity at the top. But there are distinct reasons for addressing
inequality at the top, not just the bottom.
And, as a matter of morals, rhetoric, and political economy, it is hard
to be sure whether addressing the two kinds of inequality is more a case of
substitution – you can only do one, at most, as Ed believes – or of
complementarity, where they are best seen as parts of the same enterprise.
1 comment:
I found this post very enlightening. Thanks for it.
I was struck by the comment that disutility from rising inequality, "reflects that we are a competitive social animal." My intuition on this point - and it is only an intuition - is opposite: that the disutility is more likely attributable to a widely shared assumption that the benefits anyone gets from social and economic cooperation are significantly due to participation in a joint enterprise. When the distribution of benefits is so skewed, it seems there is some kind of cheating going on. Joint participation is not yielding joint gains.
I think this thought is actually reflected later in the post, where you say, "such radical inequality as we have today undermines the sense of shared membership and enterprise that you may need for a successful democratic society."
Again, thanks for the post.
David Hasen
Post a Comment