My prior blogpost offered some background regarding Zach
Liscow’s “Democratic Law and Economics.” Liscow has been in the forefront among those
questioning the merits of following the “double distortion” line of argument to
conclude that “legal rules” or other regulatory policy should respond purely to
efficiency concerns, leaving distribution to be handled by the “tax system.”
While earlier work by Liscow and others (such as Sanchirico)
has challenged the accuracy and completeness of the assumptions that underlie
the admonition that distributional issues be ignored outside the “tax” realm,
here he accepts the analysis, at least arguendo, but says: What if following it
leads to too little redistribution because voters, while not otherwise averse
to it, really dislike cash transfers? (This is the demogrant side of the
Mirrlees tax model.) While the paper’s formal model defines this as a universal
aversion among voters to cash transfers (held even by poor people who would
receive the transfers), its textual discussion invokes beliefs about
entitlement to pre-tax market income. So we might think of it informally as
concerning the higher tax rates that are needed to fund demogrants, rather than
about the demogrants themselves.
The paper further posits that this is not generalized
anti-redistributive sentiment, but merely reflects “policy mental accounts.”
This draws on the behavioral economics insight that how an individual chooses
to spend a given dollar may reflect which pot of money or transaction he
assigns it to – leading to departures from consistent rational choice, although
perhaps understandable as a heuristic or rough rule of thumb to guide choice.
This in turn implies that voters (presumed to influence
policy outcomes) who oppose high tax rates to fund large demogrants might be
perfectly happy with redistribution accomplished by different means. Perhaps one
might think of this as involving the endowment effect on the tax side (i.e.,
coding precluded market returns differently than those that were first earned
then taxed), plus greater tolerance of in-kind than cash benefits on the
benefit side.
The paper therefore posits that inefficient redistribution
through legal rules might be an overall policy improvement if there is space
for it, but not for the first-best of doing it the Kaplow-Shavell way.
Here is a very simple example that I think can be used to
help illustrate the paper’s analysis. It’s taken from one of the central cases
discussed in the paper, but here I spell it out a bit more.
Suppose the Department of Transportation (DOT) is deciding
whether to spend $$ saving a rich person an hour of travel time (via airport
upgrades), or a poor person the same hour (via mass transit upgrades). Suppose
further that, based on willingness to pay, the rich person values the hour
saved at $63, and the poor person at only $25. (The paper derives this from actual
data noted in the paper.
OPTION 1, spending the money on mass transit, benefits the
poor person by $25 and the rich person by zero.
OPTION 2, spending
the money on airports, benefits the poor person by zero and the rich person by
$63.
Cost-benefit analysis, as done at the DOT and elsewhere,
commonly uses willingness to pay to discern value. So the “efficient” choice is
Option 2, spending the money to help rich people because they place greater
value on their time. Instead choosing Option 1, e.g., based on valuing people’s
time equally and then using benefit to the poor as a tiebreaker, is
inconsistent with the view that only the tax system should consider
distributional issues.
Let’s now further strengthen the case for Option 2. Using it
in lieu of Option 1, but with the addition of a cash transfer from the rich
taxpayer to the poor taxpayer, can create a Pareto improvement relative to
choosing Option 1.
Again, under Option 1 the parties gain 25 (poor) and 0
(rich).
Under Option 2, they gain 0 (poor) and 63 (rich).
Suppose we adopt Option 2 but the rich person pays the poor
person anywhere between $26 and $62 in cash.
Under Option 3a (Option 2 plus a $26 side payment,) they
gain 26 (poor) and 37 (rich).
Under Option 3b (Option 2 plus a $62 side payment), they
gain $62 (poor) and $1 rich).
Both of these options are Pareto-superior vs. Option 1. So,
while this is not exactly the double distortion argument in action, it supports
the same conclusion: Do the most efficient thing possible outside the tax
system (using willingness to pay as people’s own measure of utility effects on
them), and then, with the economic pie having been made as large as possible,
use tax-funded cash grants to create a Pareto improvement relative to the case
where we used inefficient legal rules to address distributional concerns.
This is a highly stylized and simplified example. But it’s
useful to illustrate the line of argument in the Liscow paper. In effect, he
accepts the entire thing at least for argument’s sake, but adds a political
economy constraint: Suppose that in practice Option 3a or b would happen, in a
mass society as opposed to one with just one rich and poor person negotiating,
only via higher labor income taxes to fund larger demogrants. And suppose that
aversion to high taxes or cash grants means that 3a and b simply won’t happen.
So our only choices are Option 1 or Option 2.
Suppose further that, due to other aspects of voter belief
systems, they’d be fine with selecting Option 1 – for example, based on the
belief that people’s time should count equally and that tiebreakers favoring
the poor are okay. But if the regulators believe that only efficiency should
drive non-tax decisions, we’ll get Option 2.
In effect, the paper argues that Option 1 might actually be
better than Option 2, if we assume both (a) that there is too little
redistribution overall due to mental accounting rule disparaging high tax rates
and cash grants, and (b) that there will be no marginal redistributive effects
to the choice of Option 2 over Option 1. (In effect, nothing will happen
towards implementing Option 3 variants.) So the DOT should employ
distributional analysis, rather than purely efficiency-driven cost-benefit
analysis, in the course of deciding whether it’s better to implement Option 1
or Option 2.
Choosing Option 1 might be here viewed as a standard “leaky
bucket” problem in redistribution. The rich lose $63 while the poor gain $25,
causing the analysis to depend at least in part on the marginal utility of
these values at the applicable income levels. And again, the fact that one might
have been able to use a less leaky bucket, if the public didn’t object to the
standard optimal tax model, is ruled out of bounds as politically unavailable.
The if-then logic of
the paper is unassailable. It’s a basic second-best thing, aka, the best
shouldn’t be the enemy of the better-than-nothing. If there are two paths to
addressing distributional concerns, and the better one is unavailable in
circumstances where the worse one might be available, then of course one
shouldn’t rule out the latter, but should duly consider it.
The harder and more interesting question concerns whether
and to what extent it might have significant policy relevance. Here are some
quick thoughts about that:
1) Assuming voter
control, or positing a fixable asymmetry? The paper posits that voter
influence over political outcomes makes it relevant that people have
inconsistent views, such that they might dislike redistribution done via taxes
and cash benefits, but be fine with it when done by means that a welfarist with
an advanced economic understanding of policy instruments might deem clearly
inferior. The posited set of viewpoints strikes me as clearly plausible. The
assumption that voters actually influence political outcomes sufficiently
strikes me as less so. There are well-known studies by the likes of Martin
Gilens, Larry Bartels, Benjamin Page, etc., suggesting that the policy views of
the 99% have startlingly little influence on actual policy choices in Washington.
However, there is a different reason why the paper’s line of
argument might be politically efficacious. Tax policymaking in Washington
occurs in a highly politically charged realm in which the players are only
marginally subject to influence by what people in the academic and think tank
realms are saying. (An example of such influence, however, might be recent
academic work by the likes of Diamond, Saez, and Zucman pushing out the Overton
window so that 70 percent top bracket income tax rates, along with the use of
wealth taxes or similar instruments, are now considered more plausible than
they were previously.)
But regulatory policy et al is potentially subject to
area-specific influence by specialists and experts, who might even have some
discretion despite any political overlords from the Executive Branch or
Congress who have the power to rein them in. If they have been thinking that
the regulatory process should look solely at efficiency, because that is the
climate of intellectual thought under which they have been trained (whether or
not they are actually familiar with Atkinson-Stiglitz or Kaplow-Shavell), then
it’s not impossible that suasion to the effect that distributional
considerations should count here too might affect their judgments.
In other words, one could claim in support of the efficacy
of the Liscow paper’s project that it’s addressing an asymmetry, in which the
tax realm doesn’t much follow optimal tax theory recommendations re. what it
should do, but the regulatory realm does follow the prescription that one
should leave all distributional issues to the tax system. Moving towards
distribution-conscious cost-benefit analysis might conceivably make a
difference here, subject to the “political general equilibrium” question of how
this will actually play out in the end overall.
2) General
equilibrium political playout: ‘political Coase theorem” versus the baseball
game metaphor – As the Liscow paper concedes, the
distribution-conscious approach that it urges for regulatory policymaking might
not matter after all if what David Weisbach, among others, has dubbed the
“political Coase theorem” might apply at the end of the day.
As background, the actual Coase Theorem that’s being invoked
here holds that, if transaction costs are zero, it will make no allocative
difference – although it might make a distributive difference – whether, say,
(a) I have a right to pollute unless you pay me to stop, or (b) you have a
right to stop me from polluting unless I pay you to let me do it. Either way,
with zero transaction costs it “doesn’t matter” – in terms of allocative
outcomes – which way one allocates the initial right. The idea is that the
higher-valuing user will end up possessing the right. E.g., if I value
polluting at $10 and you disvalue it at $12, then either (a) you’ll pay me
between $10 and $12 to forbear if you have the initial entitlement, or (b) I’ll
ascertain that I can’t buy the right to pollute from you at the max I’d be
willing to pay ($10). So either way, the pollution doesn’t happen. (Of course,
the Coase Theorem’s main message actually is that transaction costs are why it
might matter who gets the right – not that it generally doesn’t matter.)
Here are two versions of what proponents have called the
“political Coase theorem,” adapted to my earlier example with the choice
between mass transit and airport expenditure to reduce either a poor or a rich
person’s travel time.
Version 1: if the poor person has the power to get mass
transit spending that she values at $25 agreed to, in lieu of airport spending
that the rich person values at $63, the latter offers the former between $26
and $62 to agree to the latter. So the latter, rather than the former, ends up
happening.
As adapted to more real world regulatory choices, Weisbach has
noted the possibility that groups potentially subject to inefficient
redistribution have an incentive to offer a Pareto deal in which the
redistribution is instead done efficiently. This creates surplus that all can
share, so one might ask: Why doesn’t this just happen? (In that case, the power
to threaten inefficient regulation might matter, but one wouldn’t expect
actually to observe it.)
The answer to the question “Why won’t that just happen?”
seems pretty clear. As per the Coase Theorem in its standard application, what
about transaction costs? Inertia, information costs, disaggregated political
power so that different principals cover different policy areas and can’t
readily trade with each other, etc., are important enough (I’d argue) that we
shouldn’t simply presume that this trade is the ordinary course of things.
Sure, it’s a relevant consideration, but if anything the presumption might
often lie in the other direction (Why would it be able to happen?)
Version 2: If Congress has specific distributional goals
that it pursues coherently and consistently, then in a sense it really won’t
care what the regulators do. Or more precisely, even if it doesn’t directly
rein them in, it will simply adjust its distributional bottom line so that
distribution comes out in aggregate the same as if the regulators had pursued
efficiency alone.
I think hardened law and economics types may be prone to
finding this line of reasoning more persuasive than it actually is, because
they are used to thinking about consistent rational choice by an individual
with coherent preferences. But in politics you get all the issues of collective
choice, along with pervasive agency costs that include political actors’
frequently greater interest in such things as personal credit-claiming, blame
avoidance, and symbolic gesturing, than in substantive outcomes. Thus, even
insofar as individuals fulfill the rational actor model of optimization under coherent
and consistently followed preferences, collective choice institutions in a
modern mass society should not be expected to do this.
Once again, while obviously one has to think about the
possibility that Congress will undo (or directly rein in) distributionally
minded agencies that are not adhering to pure efficiency (as well as those that
ARE adhering to pure efficiency), there is really no reason here for a general
presumption that it just won’t matter. That, rather, is the question to be
asked.
Here is a model I prefer to the “political Coase theorem”
for thinking about why, say, the left or the right might pursue particular
distributional (or other) fights as zealously as they sometimes do. Each time
you win a battle, you’re that one battle ahead, and it won’t necessarily be
offset elsewhere even if outcomes aren’t entirely independent and uncorrelated.
Suppose a baseball team figures to win about half of its
games. Bottom of the ninth with two outs, they’re down by one run but have the
tying and winning runs in scoring position. So if the batter gets a hit they
win, if he makes an out they lose.
Either way, they’re still a .500 team over the long run. But they’re one game ahead if he gets a game-winning hit, relative to the case where he makes the third out. And there’s no particular reason to think that this will be automatically offset. A win today doesn’t, at least inherently, make a loss tomorrow more likely than it would otherwise have been.
Either way, they’re still a .500 team over the long run. But they’re one game ahead if he gets a game-winning hit, relative to the case where he makes the third out. And there’s no particular reason to think that this will be automatically offset. A win today doesn’t, at least inherently, make a loss tomorrow more likely than it would otherwise have been.
Christian College Bangalore is one of the best college in Bangalore. Christian College provides bsc course and bba courses. Visit Bsc optometry college in bangalore
ReplyDeleteHello everyone, Are you into trading or just wish to give it a try, please becareful on the platform you choose to invest on and the manager you choose to manage your account because that’s where failure starts from be wise. After reading so much comment i had to give trading tips a try, I have to come to the conclusion that binary options pays massively but the masses has refused to show us the right way to earn That’s why I have to give trading tips the accolades because they have been so helpful to traders . For a free masterclass strategy kindly contact (paytondyian699@gmail.com) for a free masterclass strategy. He'll give you a free tutors on how you can earn and recover your losses in trading for free..
ReplyDelete