Yesterday at the colloquium, Ruth Mason discussed her
paper, Citizenship Taxation. I enjoyed
reading it enough to conclude that I may want to write about this topic as
well. (I generally agree with the paper,
but it’s a rich topic and perhaps a fruitful area for me to deploy some of my
interests and approaches.)
Here are some of the points from my notes that I
thought worth discussing.
(1) The U.S.
as outlier (again!).
Here we go again.
To paraphrase Ray Davies in a 1960s Kinks song, “we’re not like anybody
else.” The U.S. is the only country to
impose (at least in theory) worldwide taxation on all non-resident
citizens. Other countries may tax some
non-residents on a worldwide basis, via the use of standards other than just
current year physical presence to determine who is really still a member of the
domestic community, but no one else does it flat out based on citizenship.
Other examples: we don’t have a VAT, our statutory
rate for corporations is unusually high, and in the international realm we
employ deferral / foreign tax credits far more extensively than anyone else.
Now, everybody else could be wrong and we could be
right. Or our circumstances could be
distinctive. But it is natural to
wonder, given, for example, the “wisdom of crowds” line of argument.
(2) Benefit
tax rationales.
The literature discussing citizenship-based taxation
often employs a benefit tax rationale.
On the one hand, U.S. citizens living abroad aren’t using the roads,
etc. They also generally can’t get U.S.
public assistance, or use healthcare subsidies that apply within the U.S.,
etc. On the other hand, in theory the
U.S. Army is protecting them, plus they have the valuable option to return,
which lots of other people might pay good money for if it were on sale.
All this might call perhaps for an intermediate U.S.
tax burden on U.S. citizens living abroad - which we actually have, given
section 911(b), which permits excluding about $100,000 of earned income, and
the allowance of foreign tax credits.
But benefit tax rationales are not widely accepted these days, as
compared to ability to pay, which of course raises the core question here:
Whose ability to pay?
Suppose that, by reason of my living abroad, the U.S.
government saved a marginal $10,000 that it would otherwise have spent giving
me services. Even without any normative
attachment to benefit taxation, it might make sense to reduce the U.S. tax bill
I would otherwise have incurred by $10,000, as this properly aligns my
incentive regarding where to live, from the fiscal standpoint and assuming that
there are no other relevant considerations.
But not much of what the U.S. government does on my behalf invites this
sort of marginal cost analysis.
(3) Defining “us” versus “them.”
Here is the nub of the issue. From a utilitarian standpoint, everyone in
the world matters equally. Numerous other
philosophical approaches agree that everyone counts the same in the relevant
sense, although they have other ways of implementing the idea that everyone
matters equally.
But just as individuals, rather than being perfect
altruists, generally act for their own benefit and that of loved ones, so it is
generally accepted that countries can care primarily just about “us” (the
members of the national community), as opposed to “them” (everyone else). Indeed, just like a buyer and seller in a
market negotiation, it is widely considered fine if everyone would like to
extract as much money from each other as possible, albeit subject to rules of
honesty and fair dealing, not doing bad things, and acting altruistically in
extreme cases (e.g., rescue when you see someone drowning, seeking to prevent
genocide abroad).
Let’s just take it as given that this personal,
family, or community-based selfishness can be justified philosophically. Many regard it as a prudentially required
exception to universal morality (we don’t have to be saints, especially when
everyone else isn’t being a saint). I
gather that Ronald Dworkin tried to fit it into his philosophical system more
holistically, but I don’t generally find myself in agreement with his full
approach.
But even taking all this as given, it is difficult to
find firm normative footing for the determination of who fits into our
community. Personally, I care about the
people I care about (and for close family members or other associates, there’d
be an argument that I ought to care even if I didn’t). But, in the impersonal setting of a national
mass community, it is hard to establish definite guideposts re. what we are
trying to do.
If I am a citizen who goes abroad for a month, I’m
surely a full U.S. person for the year (not just 11/12). Arguably the same, whether or not we choose
to impose full citizenship taxation, if I go abroad for three years but always
plan to return.
If I am here illegally, I definitely should count
normatively, at least to a degree. (Not
to dive into the murky, for me, waters of immigration law and policy.) This is why most of us would insist on
allowing illegals to get treated in the ER when they face dire medical
problems. And we shouldn’t be happy
about having a two-class society here, the Americans here and the others,
whether the latter are lawful guest workers or illegals. But I digress. The point here is simply that residence
inevitably counts – we care more about people who are right in our faces than
about others – but it is not all that counts given that I can be away from what
continues to be my community.
What we mean by the “us” whom we agree to care about,
once we have accepted an approach that mainly limits altruism to the members of
one’s own community, is most likely going to be multi-dimensional, rather than
turning on a single metric such as citizenship.
Specifying a legal rule to define the members of our community (who may
be subject to at least some elements of worldwide taxation, even when they are
abroad) may involve the usual tradeoff between complexity and accuracy. But as I discuss below, there may also be
efficiency benefits to a multi-factor approach.
(4) What
about “them”?
For those in
the “them” category, in principle we might want to revenue-maximize – that is,
get as much money from them (in real economic incidence terms) as we can. This is not diabolical; it’s just how
transactional counterparties commonly deal with each other.
This of course leads to the Monty Python Principle:
“Tax all foreigners living abroad.” So
why don’t we try to do that? Well,
obviously, it would not be a great idea to try, at least without more of a
hook. We don’t have jurisdiction, we
don’t have information, it would violate comity and get them really angry, they
would retaliate in various ways that we wouldn’t like, etcetera. And more generally, cooperation for mutual
gain is always a good idea when it can be done.
But, when we turn to the treatment of “us,” it’s worth keeping in mind
that there is a hypothetical perspective from which we might like to tax all
foreigners living abroad.
(5)
The basic paradox: if you’re “us” and we care about you, you lose.
Once we accept that we can’t, and generally won’t even
try, to “tax all foreigners living abroad,” something that is at least facially
paradoxical arises when we consider taxing at least some nonresident citizens
on their foreign source income. This tax
burdens the individual who has to pay it.
So we are effectively saying: “If we care about you, we’re going to
burden you. If we don’t care about you,
because we have decided not to classify you as a member of our community, then
we’re not going to burden you.
Now, one thing we clearly do care about, when taxing
members of our community whether they are currently residents or not, is
deadweight loss that we impose on them through our rules. We don’t necessarily care directly about
deadweight loss that is imposed on non-members, since we are at least mainly
excluding all “thems” from our social welfare function, but for “us” it
matters. And this is pretty much the
proof that the current U.S. regime for taxing nonresident citizens is defective
and needs to be revised. It appears to
impose a lot of deadweight loss, from compliance burdens and the like, relative
to the revenue that is actually raised.
This results, for example, from tax filing requirements who owe little
or no U.S. tax (e.g., due to the earned income exclusion plus foreign tax
credits). Now, we may gain valuable
information from the filing (or, rather, we would if people actually filed),
but this is still a serious concern.
A question meriting further thought: Why don’t we
extend more transfers or other social welfare, safety-net style benefits to
non-resident citizens? Perhaps there are
good reasons for not doing so, but at the least it requires further
thought. Presumably if we had greater
tax-transfer integration, such as via a Mirrleesean demogrant / income tax
system, we would at least consider giving the demogrant to non –resident
“us.” Or perhaps not, if there are
particular incentive issues to keep in mind here. But worth some thought in any event.
Circling back to “us” versus “them”: Suppose we can tax U.S. citizens living abroad, but
we classify these individuals as “them” rather than “us.” Only, suppose that, because they are arguably
“us,” we can get away with it – other countries won’t start to scream,
retaliate, etcetera. Then we would have
a “them”-based reason for imposing the tax (and also for withholding welfare
benefits and not caring so much about deadweight loss). In short, it could be the one case of “Tax
all foreigners living abroad” that we could actually pull off. And this would imply not caring so much about
deadweight loss that we impose on nonresident citizens. But it does strike me as a bit harsh.
(6) Two-stage
analysis for immigrants: before & after they become “us”
Let’s leave aside all the issues about illegal
residents, as that’s a very different topic and neither raised by Ruth’s paper
nor an area of personal expertise on my part.
Instead, let’s consider people who might like to immigrate to the U.S.,
at least conditionally on comparing it to other places where they might choose
to live, and whom we are considering admitting to our community
voluntarily. They are not here yet, and
suppose they will only come here if we let them.
I bring up these people because Ruth’s paper rightly
expands the scope of the inquiry to them, by noting that, when we are
considering the taxation of nonresident U.S. citizens (as well as green
cardholders) on their worldwide income, prospective immigrants are among those
whom we should have in mind. Suppose,
for example, that immigrants whom we would like to attract would take note of the
U.S. worldwide tax system for citizens and green cardholders, when they are
deciding where to go.
Since prospective immigrants are not “us” yet, we
might want to maximize the sum of (1) the present value of the money we could
get by admitting them, plus (2) the positive externalities that their presence
would generate for us.
In terms of (1), you can be crude about it, if you
like, and charge an upfront fee for a passport.
Malta and Cyprus do this, and can charge extra-high fees because they
can offer EU passports. Several
Caribbean countries also sell passports, albeit for less as they can’t offer an
EU passport. The closest the U.S. comes
to charging an upfront fee is via our EB-5 immigrant investor program.
For the most part, however, we are a bit more decorous
about exchanging money for admission to our community, in that we allow
immigrants – once admitted – to pay under the installment plan, rather than
up-front. That is, immigrants generally
can be expected to generate positive tax revenues for the U.S. by reason of
paying income and other taxes once here.
We probably should admit more of these people than we
do, especially if positive externalities are significant too (as I suspect
they are). But from the standpoint of
efficient pricing, telling prospective green cardholders in particular that at
some point they would be getting taxed on their worldwide income even if they
weren’t living in the U.S. might not be an optimal way to structure the “fee.” We’re telling them, “It’s going to cost you
even if and when you don’t find yourself living in the U.S., which might be the
scenario in which they would value it the least. I have heard it said that well-heeled
foreigners who are thinking of spending significant time in the U.S., and who
have access to temporary admission under various of our categories, often are
advised against seeking a green card.
(7) Relevance
of multiple margins (citizenship & residence)
As David Gamage notes in a paper that he presented at
our colloquium last year, it is often preferable to have many small
distortions, rather than a few large ones.
Citizenship-based taxation may induce people to renounce U.S.
citizenship. Residence-based taxation
can encourage them to make sure they are out of the country for at least the
requisite time each year. A rule based
on domicile may discourage having one here.
And so forth. But a standard that
relies on several different factors may end up, with proper design, inducing
less tax-motivated distortion overall.
Obviously, the fiend or goblin (to avoid saying “devil,” as that’s
become such a cliché) is in the details.
(8) Foreign
taxes
I’ve written extensively (such as here, here, and
here) against the desirability of providing full and immediate foreign tax
credits in the setting of business taxation.
My main argument is that foreign taxes are a cost from the unilateral
domestic standpoint, hence we should want domestic taxpayers to be foreign tax
cost-conscious. Indeed, straightforward
deductibility for foreign taxes (so they will be treated as equivalent to other
outlays or forgone inflows) is the way
to go, from a unilateral national welfare standpoint, unless there is more to
think about here. As it happens, I agree
that there actually is more to think about in the setting of corporate income
taxation, e.g., because if profits show up in a tax haven that may be a “tag”
for discerning profit-shifting away from home, whence my conclusion that, for
U.S. companies, we might favor a better-than-deductibility,
worse-than-creditability bottom line effect.
Well-designed anti-tax haven rules can have this effect.
Exemption is an implicit deductibility system. Of course, if you limit exemption for the
foreign source income of resident companies via anti-tax haven rules, you may
get back into that intermediate range (or even beyond, if the rules are poorly
designed)
How do these arguments apply to taxing nonresident
individuals on their foreign source earned income? While the topic may require further thought,
my initial thought is that a similar basic analysis does indeed apply. Suppose, for example, that an American is
deciding whether to work abroad in lower-tax Singapore or the higher-tax
UK. It may be desirable, from a U.S.
standpoint, if he or she bases the analysis on after-foreign tax income, rather
than before-foreign tax income. After
all, from our standpoint those taxes are just a cost, as we don’t get the tax
revenues.
While it might be the case that the use of tax havens
at the expense of the domestic tax base is not as much a problem for individuals’
earned income as it is for companies’ reported profits, that would only push
harder towards the deductibility, as opposed to creditability, side of the
spectrum. And even if we treated foreign
taxes on U.S. individuals’ foreign earned income as effectively deductible,
rather than creditable, then (assuming a treaty-compliant design, which might
not be impossible) we might decide to apply a significantly lower tax rate to
foreign than domestic earned income, e.g., for the reasons I will discuss next.
The exclusion under Code section 911(b) for about
$100,000 of qualifying foreign earned income has the desirable effect of
pushing away from effective creditability.
You can’t claim foreign tax credits with respect to foreign earned
income that we don’t tax. But that
doesn’t tell us whether zero is the right rate (perhaps even without being so
capped), or is too low a rate. That
depends on other considerations.
(9)
Foreign earned income
Even leaving aside the treatment of foreign taxes, should
we tax U.S. individuals’ foreign earned income at the full domestic rate? An “ability to pay” perspective would suggest
that the answer is yes. But there may be
an efficiency argument (from a national welfare perspective) in favor of a
lower rate. This argument is borrowed
from Mihir Desai’s and Jim Hines’ analysis of “national ownership neutrality”
(“NON”).
Suppose the following, as Desai and Hines do in the
NON context: Each “outbound” dollar is replaced by an “inbound” dollar from a
foreigner who earns income that is taxable in the U.S. by reason of the
outflow. Translating it from their
context to mine, let’s take a simple case, grossly overstated by me just so one
can grasp the argument. Suppose that, if
I leave NYU for a year to teach at a foreign university (which will pay me in
lieu of NYU’s doing so), NYU will hire a foreigner to teach in the U.S. in my
place, and pay U.S. tax on the substitute salary. At a rough approximation, even if the U.S.
gave me an incentive to visit abroad by not taxing my foreign earnings (and
again, the U.S. may have no direct reason to view payments to the foreign tax
authority as equivalent to paying U.S. tax), it would not have lost any
domestic tax base. U.S. salaries would
be the same, and the IRS would be taxing that foreigner, who would otherwise
have escaped its clutches.
Suppose we take this hypothetical to be appropriate –
as Desai and Hines do in the setting of cross-border business investment. (They of course do not make any such claim,
or at least they haven’t yet, with regard my hypothetical, which they might
join other readers in finding fanciful.)
They then argue that the optimal U.S. tax rate on the foreign source
income is zero, so that there will be no distortion at the margin of U.S.
companies deciding how much to invest abroad rather than at home. (Again, the claim is that the lost domestic
investment is actually zero, net of the inbound flows it induces that would not
otherwise have occurred.)
I think this argument is wrong, because we are trying
to balance distortions at multiple margins, not reduce them to zero at some
arbitrarily chosen margins while they remain high at other margins. But I will go so far as to agree with Desai
and Hines that it may support a lower
U.S. tax rate on resident companies’ foreign source income than that on all
companies’ U.S. source income.
Does this argument apply to foreign earned income of
U.S. individuals? I suspect that the
extent to which it applies is greater than zero, albeit less than 100 percent. Americans who work abroad may indeed often
leave slots that get filled by someone else, including a foreigner. (There may also be a positive spillover if
the result is to increase other Americans’ domestic earnings by reason of the
slot I left open for the year.) So there
may be an argument for taxing foreign earned income of U.S. individuals at a
lower rate than their U.S. earned income, even wholly leaving aside the issue
of how to treat foreign taxes.
There may also be positive externalities when U.S.
individuals work abroad. One hopes that
they are effective ambassadors, spreading goodwill abroad towards those of our
ilk, rather than being the stereotypical “ugly Americans.” Plus, if they learn about life abroad and
then return here, the things they learn may enrich life for other
Americans. One of the absolutely
greatest things about our country is the extent to which we’ve been a global
melting pot, not only because people come here from abroad and are accepted,
but also because it makes us (at least on the coasts) more cosmopolitan and international,
to our great hedonic benefit. Or at
least that’s how I view it.
(10) Exit
tax
Code section 877A generally requires tax expatriates to
pay tax on a deemed sale of their assets for fair market value. The tax only applies to net gain in excess of
$600,000. This exit tax makes up for the
fact that, once you’re gone, the built-in gain from the period when you were
still a U.S. citizen is unlikely ever to be taxed here. So one could view it as anti-windfall gain, rather
than as aiming to be punitive.
That characterization of the provision would be more
solid and beyond dispute if we taxed net asset appreciation at death, rather than
allowing a tax-free step-up in basis at that time. But, for what it’s worth, the provision can
indeed reduce lock-in on the part of individuals who are considering
expatriating.
Here is a further issue that might be worth thinking about. Suppose someone who might owe estate tax liability at death expatriates before that point. Proponents of the estate tax might support treating expatriation as a triggering event for levying the tax. Not just because "You're dead to us now," but to avoid creating the incentive to expatriate for that reason.
21 comments:
I like your articles about Tax Policy, very useful in my job. Using your blog i can surely say to my customers: "trust my paper", because I'm using most reliable information sources.
Hello, I am visiting often, sometimes dayly, good articles, amazing giveaways, thank you very much for al of this!
Tax Lawyer
Now you can pay for essay and Get the best quality essay writing service which will provide you with the quality and proper essay. Our apex writers are professional writers so they what it takes to write the perfect essay.Order our service now!
Many students are going for the IELTS exams so they need proper training. We provide the best IELTS exam training which will provide you with the best methods to help you score good marks in IELTS exams.Also now you can get the IELTS preparation in Lahore Order us now
Explainer videos are made to explain the concept of the product easily and can promote it in a short amount of time. Also, they are very attractive and interesting so they gain peoples attention. Get the best explainer video service at https://www.explainermojo.com/ which will promote your product and users will understand the product in a short amount of time.
As a student, you know that sometimes you just can’t keep up with all your deadlines. EduBirdie say that they can take essays off your hands for you when you need it the most. With so many sites turning out to be a scam though, can you trust them to be legit? Our EduBirdie review has everything you need to know. If you are looking for information about “ban edubirdie
”, welcome to Scamfighter!
As as a student you will find yourself stuck with an essay or assignment that you can barely understand. If that is the case, don't hesitate to ask for essay help as that will guarantee you a better grade.
Yummmmmmm just picked up some today from spot in my hood. Bought some @cure420farms Jh, harvest date is 7/18. Very very nice. I think I have done concentrates of this strain and it was, so so. This flower is legit! https://wendymccormick.com/white-widow-cannabis-seeds/
Ohh, it's very interesting. It's difficult to believe, but my next lesson will be about taxes. And I may use some info from this article prime essay writing . It's amazing. Thank you for writing this.
Hi! If you want to have the best discussion board post and not to put aside all the fun and activity in your students life, we offer you a chance to make an order now and have every opportunity right now.
This tax article doesnt always have o be that bad
FTM 2017 download
The FTM 2017 version is a great way to keep track of your family history. It is always good to have an updated version of a family tree when someone is looking for new relatives or just trying to find out where their roots lie. Family tree maker 2017 makes it easy for you to do this.
FTM 2017 makes it easy to keep track of the people who are in the family. So we can create a simple chart that records everything from the birth of a child to their death and marriages and divorces. If someone has divorced, they may need to go back and look at the family tree to make sure that everyone is listed correctly. It is crucial if any children are involved in a divorce process.
Wow it was informative.
Thanks for your thoughts. It was helpful cause now i learned exactly new information about citizenship taxation. I think you shoud post this information on Instagram where a large amount of users could see it and don`t forget to use the services of https://viplikes.net/buy-instagram-followers and quickly boost their number.
In Sunkkan Saunkne we see Punjabi film actresses Sargun Mehta and Nimrat Khaira along with Amy Virk, and Canadian actress Amy Virk gets married to Sargun Mehta. Saukane Punjabi movie download hd one click
Xavier Musk net worth and biography In this article we will tell you about biography of Xavier Musk net worth, his early life is education his age. Xavier Musk who is the son of Elon Musk was born in the musk family in 2004.
Hello, I am visiting often, sometimes dayly, good articles, amazing giveaways, thank you very much for al of this! how to make a capricorn woman jealous
Post a Comment