I've just sent the publisher final revisions to my submitted manuscript on literature and high-end inequality. The book's projected publication date is April 1, 2020, or just over 5 months from now.
The current working title, which could change again, is Literature and Inequality: Nine Perspectives from the Age of Napoleon Through the First Gilded Age.
An earlier draft was 110,000 words. It's now down to less than 92,000 words. I think a key reason that it was previously longer was that my writing in what was a new area for me caused me initially to be a bit too prolix, just as early-career academics can sometimes be. I feel that I've been able to add discipline and focus. And there are certainly, at a minimum, some well-written bits, if I do say so myself.
I really had to teach myself a new genre in doing this, without much in the way of role models. And at some point I'll have to ask myself the question: Do I now do this again by writing Part 2? (1920s through the present.) It's hard to imagine now feeling sufficiently motivated, as it wouldn't be an easy project to plan, research, and write. But never say never.
My current next project, other than finalizing my recently posted draft on digital services taxes et al, is to write a short (50,000 to 60,000 word) sequel to my earlier book on international tax policy. I think there's room for and a point to writing such a book, and it's also way easier than writing a literature book sequel. It would also probably have a higher floor, albeit a lower ceiling, on public success than writing a literature book sequel.
Sufficient public success of the literature book would certainly push me towards greater likelihood of writing its sequel. But I know from this biz (and from books by friends that have fallen short commercially of meeting their perhaps too-high hopes and expectations) that breaking through isn't easy.
Unfair but balanced commentary on tax and budget policy, contemporary U.S. politics and culture, and whatever else happens to come up
Wednesday, October 30, 2019
NYU Tax Policy Colloquium, week 9 - paper by John Friedman on colleges and intergenerational mobility
Yesterday at the colloquium, John Friedman presented work in progress from his big-data project with Raj Chetty, Emmanuel Saez, Nicholas Turner, and Danny Yagan. This is a very important and interesting project,. However, because it's work-in-progress involving IRS tax data, I won't comment on or link to the draft(s) we saw or heard about yesterday. And as the sessions are off the record, what I'll discuss here, rather than either the work presented or the PM discussions, is issues raised by the research.
Friedman et al have access to data (not to put it passively - they've done a great deal of work to create usable data) that permits them to link (1) college admissions, (2) the applicants' parental / household income, (3) the applicants' test scores, (4) where they ended up going to college, and (5) their labor income (for people born in 1980-82) thirty to thirty-two years out.
The U.S. is a big country, so there's a lot of information here that can be analyzed in various ways. For example, they can look at such questions as how people with different parental incomes and the same test scores differentially attended colleges in particular tiers, how people with the same parental incomes and test scores but who went to colleges in different tiers ended up doing in the labor market at age 30 to 32, etc.
A lot of interesting information can come out of this. For example, what sort of "value add" if any do top tier schools appear to have, in terms of subsequent labor income? Are colleges differentially picking more high income, middle income, or low income students with the same test scores? Do kids from lower income households but with good test scores end up doing better or worse in the labor market than peers from higher income households, if they go to the same schools or to different tier schools? Etcetera; you can add your own questions to this as you like.
Without reporting here on any preliminary results, let me say this. If high-tier colleges have significant value-add, as defined above, and this value-add applies to both lower-income and higher-income applicants, then they have the power to increase intergenerational mobility by tilting towards the lower income in admissions, or to reduce it by tilting towards the higher income. From a structural standpoint, they may have a lot of incentives to do the latter - that is, to offer what is in effect affirmative action for the rich, not limited to "legacies" (children of alums) or to athletes in the specialized types of sports that tend to require rich parents. That would be very unfortunate, as it would mean they were both reducing intergenerational mobility relative to the case where they were neutrally meritocratic (defining meritocracy as rewarding high test scores), and also increasing income segregation at high-tier colleges relative to what would happen if they neutrally applied such a benchmark. We will have to wait and see what the data shows, when final versions of the papers are released.
Suppose top tier colleges have a significant value-add but fewer slots than there are qualified applicants who could take advantage of it. Then there would be an analogy between top tier college admission and allocating scarce kidneys or livers to sick people in acute care wards. In each case:
1) There are more people who could derive full benefit from the scarce resource (restored health, or higher career earnings) than there are available resources. The winners will therefore discontinuously be better-off than the losers, as between people who could have made comparably productive use of the scarce resource.
2) We may be reluctant to allow use of the price mechanism to allocate the scarce resource. We don't put kidneys and livers up to auction so the richest people will get them all. In college admissions, there is obviously more opportunity for the price mechanism to operate, but we may tend not to like the idea of allowing rich kids to buy more slots by having their parents pay more.
To the extent that use of the price mechanism to allocate the scarce resources is restricted, other metrics are going to have to be used. In the case of college admissions, a strong argument could be made for favoring lower-income over higher-income applicants with close or similar test scores, especially if it's shown that the former can at least comparably benefit from the value-add. Specifically, there are two positive externalities to keep in mind. The first is reducing income segregation in top schools, so that richer, middle, and poorer kids mingle more than they would under a caste-like system. The second is increasing intergenerational income mobility, which may have broader social benefits, again in reducing the extent to which we have a hereditary caste system in our society.
If richer kids with the same test scores were disfavored, they could make arguments based on meritocratic desert to the effect that they were being treated unfairly. But this might be at least partly rebutted by noting the advantages they may have had, such as greater tutoring, in getting the same test scores.
If intergenerational mobility is low enough, we also know that it's unlikely to be as truly meritocratic as it appears to be. Income-earning "ability" seems unlikely to be sufficiently inheritable that there wouldn't be more movement up and down, in a legitimately meritocratic process, than we appear to be observing lately.
But of course, while mobility sounds good as an aim (and is good, if we dislike hereditary castes), it does mean people are moving down as well as up. Those who move down, or see their kids moving down, are not going to be made happy by it. And if they're powerful, they may be likely to resist.
I suspect that very wealthy people are more determined to ensure that their kids be the most successful ones in the next generation, whether meritocratically or not, than they are to avoid, say, paying wealth taxes. So the political playout of college admissions over time could end up being interesting and fraught.
Friedman et al have access to data (not to put it passively - they've done a great deal of work to create usable data) that permits them to link (1) college admissions, (2) the applicants' parental / household income, (3) the applicants' test scores, (4) where they ended up going to college, and (5) their labor income (for people born in 1980-82) thirty to thirty-two years out.
The U.S. is a big country, so there's a lot of information here that can be analyzed in various ways. For example, they can look at such questions as how people with different parental incomes and the same test scores differentially attended colleges in particular tiers, how people with the same parental incomes and test scores but who went to colleges in different tiers ended up doing in the labor market at age 30 to 32, etc.
A lot of interesting information can come out of this. For example, what sort of "value add" if any do top tier schools appear to have, in terms of subsequent labor income? Are colleges differentially picking more high income, middle income, or low income students with the same test scores? Do kids from lower income households but with good test scores end up doing better or worse in the labor market than peers from higher income households, if they go to the same schools or to different tier schools? Etcetera; you can add your own questions to this as you like.
Without reporting here on any preliminary results, let me say this. If high-tier colleges have significant value-add, as defined above, and this value-add applies to both lower-income and higher-income applicants, then they have the power to increase intergenerational mobility by tilting towards the lower income in admissions, or to reduce it by tilting towards the higher income. From a structural standpoint, they may have a lot of incentives to do the latter - that is, to offer what is in effect affirmative action for the rich, not limited to "legacies" (children of alums) or to athletes in the specialized types of sports that tend to require rich parents. That would be very unfortunate, as it would mean they were both reducing intergenerational mobility relative to the case where they were neutrally meritocratic (defining meritocracy as rewarding high test scores), and also increasing income segregation at high-tier colleges relative to what would happen if they neutrally applied such a benchmark. We will have to wait and see what the data shows, when final versions of the papers are released.
Suppose top tier colleges have a significant value-add but fewer slots than there are qualified applicants who could take advantage of it. Then there would be an analogy between top tier college admission and allocating scarce kidneys or livers to sick people in acute care wards. In each case:
1) There are more people who could derive full benefit from the scarce resource (restored health, or higher career earnings) than there are available resources. The winners will therefore discontinuously be better-off than the losers, as between people who could have made comparably productive use of the scarce resource.
2) We may be reluctant to allow use of the price mechanism to allocate the scarce resource. We don't put kidneys and livers up to auction so the richest people will get them all. In college admissions, there is obviously more opportunity for the price mechanism to operate, but we may tend not to like the idea of allowing rich kids to buy more slots by having their parents pay more.
To the extent that use of the price mechanism to allocate the scarce resources is restricted, other metrics are going to have to be used. In the case of college admissions, a strong argument could be made for favoring lower-income over higher-income applicants with close or similar test scores, especially if it's shown that the former can at least comparably benefit from the value-add. Specifically, there are two positive externalities to keep in mind. The first is reducing income segregation in top schools, so that richer, middle, and poorer kids mingle more than they would under a caste-like system. The second is increasing intergenerational income mobility, which may have broader social benefits, again in reducing the extent to which we have a hereditary caste system in our society.
If richer kids with the same test scores were disfavored, they could make arguments based on meritocratic desert to the effect that they were being treated unfairly. But this might be at least partly rebutted by noting the advantages they may have had, such as greater tutoring, in getting the same test scores.
If intergenerational mobility is low enough, we also know that it's unlikely to be as truly meritocratic as it appears to be. Income-earning "ability" seems unlikely to be sufficiently inheritable that there wouldn't be more movement up and down, in a legitimately meritocratic process, than we appear to be observing lately.
But of course, while mobility sounds good as an aim (and is good, if we dislike hereditary castes), it does mean people are moving down as well as up. Those who move down, or see their kids moving down, are not going to be made happy by it. And if they're powerful, they may be likely to resist.
I suspect that very wealthy people are more determined to ensure that their kids be the most successful ones in the next generation, whether meritocratically or not, than they are to avoid, say, paying wealth taxes. So the political playout of college admissions over time could end up being interesting and fraught.
Friday, October 25, 2019
Strange musical dream last night
Close to morning, I found myself either leading or watching a small rock group in a studio, rehearsing a new song, presumably to record it when the arrangement was set. Lucky us, we had John Lennon and Paul McCartney there to help with back-up vocals. Set to come in on the second verse, McCartney came up with a back-up answering vocal for the lead, under which he and John would keep singing "Baby, can you run?" Lennon changed it so it would go "Baby, can you run? Baby, can you run now?" (He messed it up and came in wrong initially, but they immediately realized this was an improvement.)
I know the notes, but would need a piano to identify them. I don't remember the lead melody, if indeed there was one. And again it was fluid whether I was watching or participating. But anyway then the alarm went off.
Certainly better than dreaming about current U.S. politics.
I know the notes, but would need a piano to identify them. I don't remember the lead melody, if indeed there was one. And again it was fluid whether I was watching or participating. But anyway then the alarm went off.
Certainly better than dreaming about current U.S. politics.
Wednesday, October 23, 2019
NYU Tax Policy Colloquium, week 8 - paper by Oei and Ring
Yesterday at the colloquium, Diane Ring presented her paper (coauthored with Shu-Yi Oei), Falling Short in the Data Age. This is not a tax paper as such, although it touches on tax topics, but grows out of the authors' interest in the rise of ubiquitous data that governments or firms can increasingly access and analyze, possibly in relation to their work, for example, on "leak-driven law" and on recent workplace shifts that are epitomized by the rise of Uber et al.
The particular angle they explore here is that technological shifts may reduce the "fall-short spaces" that people have long had as a practical matter. Here's an example that I find convenient for purposes of thinking about what they have in mind, although it isn't actually mentioned in the paper. In New York, jaywalking, while illegal, is the norm. This isn't rulelessness - there is a rule, although not everyone always follows it. The rule is that a red light is a yield sign. (I would say check-and-yield, but given how bicyclists operate in NYC you must always check in all directions even if the light is in your favor, and indeed even if you're crossing a one-way street in which no one is coming from the mandated direction.)
This is more than just a fall-short space, in the sense that New Yorkers jaywalk right in front of police who don't enforce the rule. But suppose that - at least in places where jaywalking violates norms as well as laws - there were facial recognition cameras at every corner, so that if you jaywalked you'd get a ticket, levying a fine, by mail (just as can happen when you go through a toll plaza without EZ Pass, & they photograph your license plate).
The issue that would arise then isn't (mainly) that people would be getting fined all the time. Rather, they would stop jaywalking, which would be somewhat good and somewhat bad. (The NYC norm for jaywalking is superior to the blind-obedience norm when properly executed by everyone, but it also invites greater, and potentially costly, errors in applying it.) Plus, we would have the other issues around cameras everywhere telling whomever had access to the footage where one was going all the time.
One could enrich this little example's capacity to stand in for the broader set of problems that the paper discusses by adding in discriminatory enforcement. E.g., suppose Attorney General Barr gets to decide who does and doesn't get a jaywalking ticket.
The paper has laudably broad ambitions, which combine devising a general compendium of issues and categories, with offering a couple of broad takeaways, e.g., (1) space to "fall short" of honoring all of the legal commands one faces is shrinking and this isn't all good, (2) more sophisticated and well-financed players will be especially well-equipped to take advantage of new high-data environments (although that's also likely to be true in other environments). I look forward to seeing the final version.
The particular angle they explore here is that technological shifts may reduce the "fall-short spaces" that people have long had as a practical matter. Here's an example that I find convenient for purposes of thinking about what they have in mind, although it isn't actually mentioned in the paper. In New York, jaywalking, while illegal, is the norm. This isn't rulelessness - there is a rule, although not everyone always follows it. The rule is that a red light is a yield sign. (I would say check-and-yield, but given how bicyclists operate in NYC you must always check in all directions even if the light is in your favor, and indeed even if you're crossing a one-way street in which no one is coming from the mandated direction.)
This is more than just a fall-short space, in the sense that New Yorkers jaywalk right in front of police who don't enforce the rule. But suppose that - at least in places where jaywalking violates norms as well as laws - there were facial recognition cameras at every corner, so that if you jaywalked you'd get a ticket, levying a fine, by mail (just as can happen when you go through a toll plaza without EZ Pass, & they photograph your license plate).
The issue that would arise then isn't (mainly) that people would be getting fined all the time. Rather, they would stop jaywalking, which would be somewhat good and somewhat bad. (The NYC norm for jaywalking is superior to the blind-obedience norm when properly executed by everyone, but it also invites greater, and potentially costly, errors in applying it.) Plus, we would have the other issues around cameras everywhere telling whomever had access to the footage where one was going all the time.
One could enrich this little example's capacity to stand in for the broader set of problems that the paper discusses by adding in discriminatory enforcement. E.g., suppose Attorney General Barr gets to decide who does and doesn't get a jaywalking ticket.
The paper has laudably broad ambitions, which combine devising a general compendium of issues and categories, with offering a couple of broad takeaways, e.g., (1) space to "fall short" of honoring all of the legal commands one faces is shrinking and this isn't all good, (2) more sophisticated and well-financed players will be especially well-equipped to take advantage of new high-data environments (although that's also likely to be true in other environments). I look forward to seeing the final version.
Thursday, October 17, 2019
Most wanted
Someone in our house keeps knocking over garbage cans, looking for small items that are usable as toys.
Based on character and propensity evidence that might not be admissible in a court of law, here is our chief suspect: Gary, aka the Silly Bandit.
I'd say: Butter wouldn't melt in his mouth, except I'm fairly confident that it would.
Based on character and propensity evidence that might not be admissible in a court of law, here is our chief suspect: Gary, aka the Silly Bandit.
I'd say: Butter wouldn't melt in his mouth, except I'm fairly confident that it would.
Talk at University of Toronto Law School on my new international tax paper
Yesterday at the University of Toronto Law School's Tax Law and Policy Workshop, I gave a talk concerning my new paper, "Digital Service Taxes and the Broader Shift From Determining the Source of Income to Taxing Location Specific Rents."
The slides are available here. I'll soon be posting a revised version of the paper on SSRN; the currently posted version is a bit out of date.
It was very nice seeing the folks there. But if you do enough travel, you have to take the rough with the smooth occasionally. Yesterday's fun was having a flight delay of nearly 2 hours when I had only 90 or so minutes of margin built in (due to the previous day's tax policy colloquium at NYU). By running through the airport etc. I managed to get there only 10 to 15 minutes late.
Today was almost even more fun, as the person at the hotel front desk simply forgot to make the wake-up call that they had in their book. Since it was at 4:45 am, the omission could have been rather consequential, had I not also set my phone.
The slides are available here. I'll soon be posting a revised version of the paper on SSRN; the currently posted version is a bit out of date.
It was very nice seeing the folks there. But if you do enough travel, you have to take the rough with the smooth occasionally. Yesterday's fun was having a flight delay of nearly 2 hours when I had only 90 or so minutes of margin built in (due to the previous day's tax policy colloquium at NYU). By running through the airport etc. I managed to get there only 10 to 15 minutes late.
Today was almost even more fun, as the person at the hotel front desk simply forgot to make the wake-up call that they had in their book. Since it was at 4:45 am, the omission could have been rather consequential, had I not also set my phone.
Wednesday, October 16, 2019
Tax policy colloquium, week 7: Zach Liscow, part 2
My prior blogpost offered some background regarding Zach
Liscow’s “Democratic Law and Economics.” Liscow has been in the forefront among those
questioning the merits of following the “double distortion” line of argument to
conclude that “legal rules” or other regulatory policy should respond purely to
efficiency concerns, leaving distribution to be handled by the “tax system.”
While earlier work by Liscow and others (such as Sanchirico)
has challenged the accuracy and completeness of the assumptions that underlie
the admonition that distributional issues be ignored outside the “tax” realm,
here he accepts the analysis, at least arguendo, but says: What if following it
leads to too little redistribution because voters, while not otherwise averse
to it, really dislike cash transfers? (This is the demogrant side of the
Mirrlees tax model.) While the paper’s formal model defines this as a universal
aversion among voters to cash transfers (held even by poor people who would
receive the transfers), its textual discussion invokes beliefs about
entitlement to pre-tax market income. So we might think of it informally as
concerning the higher tax rates that are needed to fund demogrants, rather than
about the demogrants themselves.
The paper further posits that this is not generalized
anti-redistributive sentiment, but merely reflects “policy mental accounts.”
This draws on the behavioral economics insight that how an individual chooses
to spend a given dollar may reflect which pot of money or transaction he
assigns it to – leading to departures from consistent rational choice, although
perhaps understandable as a heuristic or rough rule of thumb to guide choice.
This in turn implies that voters (presumed to influence
policy outcomes) who oppose high tax rates to fund large demogrants might be
perfectly happy with redistribution accomplished by different means. Perhaps one
might think of this as involving the endowment effect on the tax side (i.e.,
coding precluded market returns differently than those that were first earned
then taxed), plus greater tolerance of in-kind than cash benefits on the
benefit side.
The paper therefore posits that inefficient redistribution
through legal rules might be an overall policy improvement if there is space
for it, but not for the first-best of doing it the Kaplow-Shavell way.
Here is a very simple example that I think can be used to
help illustrate the paper’s analysis. It’s taken from one of the central cases
discussed in the paper, but here I spell it out a bit more.
Suppose the Department of Transportation (DOT) is deciding
whether to spend $$ saving a rich person an hour of travel time (via airport
upgrades), or a poor person the same hour (via mass transit upgrades). Suppose
further that, based on willingness to pay, the rich person values the hour
saved at $63, and the poor person at only $25. (The paper derives this from actual
data noted in the paper.
OPTION 1, spending the money on mass transit, benefits the
poor person by $25 and the rich person by zero.
OPTION 2, spending
the money on airports, benefits the poor person by zero and the rich person by
$63.
Cost-benefit analysis, as done at the DOT and elsewhere,
commonly uses willingness to pay to discern value. So the “efficient” choice is
Option 2, spending the money to help rich people because they place greater
value on their time. Instead choosing Option 1, e.g., based on valuing people’s
time equally and then using benefit to the poor as a tiebreaker, is
inconsistent with the view that only the tax system should consider
distributional issues.
Let’s now further strengthen the case for Option 2. Using it
in lieu of Option 1, but with the addition of a cash transfer from the rich
taxpayer to the poor taxpayer, can create a Pareto improvement relative to
choosing Option 1.
Again, under Option 1 the parties gain 25 (poor) and 0
(rich).
Under Option 2, they gain 0 (poor) and 63 (rich).
Suppose we adopt Option 2 but the rich person pays the poor
person anywhere between $26 and $62 in cash.
Under Option 3a (Option 2 plus a $26 side payment,) they
gain 26 (poor) and 37 (rich).
Under Option 3b (Option 2 plus a $62 side payment), they
gain $62 (poor) and $1 rich).
Both of these options are Pareto-superior vs. Option 1. So,
while this is not exactly the double distortion argument in action, it supports
the same conclusion: Do the most efficient thing possible outside the tax
system (using willingness to pay as people’s own measure of utility effects on
them), and then, with the economic pie having been made as large as possible,
use tax-funded cash grants to create a Pareto improvement relative to the case
where we used inefficient legal rules to address distributional concerns.
This is a highly stylized and simplified example. But it’s
useful to illustrate the line of argument in the Liscow paper. In effect, he
accepts the entire thing at least for argument’s sake, but adds a political
economy constraint: Suppose that in practice Option 3a or b would happen, in a
mass society as opposed to one with just one rich and poor person negotiating,
only via higher labor income taxes to fund larger demogrants. And suppose that
aversion to high taxes or cash grants means that 3a and b simply won’t happen.
So our only choices are Option 1 or Option 2.
Suppose further that, due to other aspects of voter belief
systems, they’d be fine with selecting Option 1 – for example, based on the
belief that people’s time should count equally and that tiebreakers favoring
the poor are okay. But if the regulators believe that only efficiency should
drive non-tax decisions, we’ll get Option 2.
In effect, the paper argues that Option 1 might actually be
better than Option 2, if we assume both (a) that there is too little
redistribution overall due to mental accounting rule disparaging high tax rates
and cash grants, and (b) that there will be no marginal redistributive effects
to the choice of Option 2 over Option 1. (In effect, nothing will happen
towards implementing Option 3 variants.) So the DOT should employ
distributional analysis, rather than purely efficiency-driven cost-benefit
analysis, in the course of deciding whether it’s better to implement Option 1
or Option 2.
Choosing Option 1 might be here viewed as a standard “leaky
bucket” problem in redistribution. The rich lose $63 while the poor gain $25,
causing the analysis to depend at least in part on the marginal utility of
these values at the applicable income levels. And again, the fact that one might
have been able to use a less leaky bucket, if the public didn’t object to the
standard optimal tax model, is ruled out of bounds as politically unavailable.
The if-then logic of
the paper is unassailable. It’s a basic second-best thing, aka, the best
shouldn’t be the enemy of the better-than-nothing. If there are two paths to
addressing distributional concerns, and the better one is unavailable in
circumstances where the worse one might be available, then of course one
shouldn’t rule out the latter, but should duly consider it.
The harder and more interesting question concerns whether
and to what extent it might have significant policy relevance. Here are some
quick thoughts about that:
1) Assuming voter
control, or positing a fixable asymmetry? The paper posits that voter
influence over political outcomes makes it relevant that people have
inconsistent views, such that they might dislike redistribution done via taxes
and cash benefits, but be fine with it when done by means that a welfarist with
an advanced economic understanding of policy instruments might deem clearly
inferior. The posited set of viewpoints strikes me as clearly plausible. The
assumption that voters actually influence political outcomes sufficiently
strikes me as less so. There are well-known studies by the likes of Martin
Gilens, Larry Bartels, Benjamin Page, etc., suggesting that the policy views of
the 99% have startlingly little influence on actual policy choices in Washington.
However, there is a different reason why the paper’s line of
argument might be politically efficacious. Tax policymaking in Washington
occurs in a highly politically charged realm in which the players are only
marginally subject to influence by what people in the academic and think tank
realms are saying. (An example of such influence, however, might be recent
academic work by the likes of Diamond, Saez, and Zucman pushing out the Overton
window so that 70 percent top bracket income tax rates, along with the use of
wealth taxes or similar instruments, are now considered more plausible than
they were previously.)
But regulatory policy et al is potentially subject to
area-specific influence by specialists and experts, who might even have some
discretion despite any political overlords from the Executive Branch or
Congress who have the power to rein them in. If they have been thinking that
the regulatory process should look solely at efficiency, because that is the
climate of intellectual thought under which they have been trained (whether or
not they are actually familiar with Atkinson-Stiglitz or Kaplow-Shavell), then
it’s not impossible that suasion to the effect that distributional
considerations should count here too might affect their judgments.
In other words, one could claim in support of the efficacy
of the Liscow paper’s project that it’s addressing an asymmetry, in which the
tax realm doesn’t much follow optimal tax theory recommendations re. what it
should do, but the regulatory realm does follow the prescription that one
should leave all distributional issues to the tax system. Moving towards
distribution-conscious cost-benefit analysis might conceivably make a
difference here, subject to the “political general equilibrium” question of how
this will actually play out in the end overall.
2) General
equilibrium political playout: ‘political Coase theorem” versus the baseball
game metaphor – As the Liscow paper concedes, the
distribution-conscious approach that it urges for regulatory policymaking might
not matter after all if what David Weisbach, among others, has dubbed the
“political Coase theorem” might apply at the end of the day.
As background, the actual Coase Theorem that’s being invoked
here holds that, if transaction costs are zero, it will make no allocative
difference – although it might make a distributive difference – whether, say,
(a) I have a right to pollute unless you pay me to stop, or (b) you have a
right to stop me from polluting unless I pay you to let me do it. Either way,
with zero transaction costs it “doesn’t matter” – in terms of allocative
outcomes – which way one allocates the initial right. The idea is that the
higher-valuing user will end up possessing the right. E.g., if I value
polluting at $10 and you disvalue it at $12, then either (a) you’ll pay me
between $10 and $12 to forbear if you have the initial entitlement, or (b) I’ll
ascertain that I can’t buy the right to pollute from you at the max I’d be
willing to pay ($10). So either way, the pollution doesn’t happen. (Of course,
the Coase Theorem’s main message actually is that transaction costs are why it
might matter who gets the right – not that it generally doesn’t matter.)
Here are two versions of what proponents have called the
“political Coase theorem,” adapted to my earlier example with the choice
between mass transit and airport expenditure to reduce either a poor or a rich
person’s travel time.
Version 1: if the poor person has the power to get mass
transit spending that she values at $25 agreed to, in lieu of airport spending
that the rich person values at $63, the latter offers the former between $26
and $62 to agree to the latter. So the latter, rather than the former, ends up
happening.
As adapted to more real world regulatory choices, Weisbach has
noted the possibility that groups potentially subject to inefficient
redistribution have an incentive to offer a Pareto deal in which the
redistribution is instead done efficiently. This creates surplus that all can
share, so one might ask: Why doesn’t this just happen? (In that case, the power
to threaten inefficient regulation might matter, but one wouldn’t expect
actually to observe it.)
The answer to the question “Why won’t that just happen?”
seems pretty clear. As per the Coase Theorem in its standard application, what
about transaction costs? Inertia, information costs, disaggregated political
power so that different principals cover different policy areas and can’t
readily trade with each other, etc., are important enough (I’d argue) that we
shouldn’t simply presume that this trade is the ordinary course of things.
Sure, it’s a relevant consideration, but if anything the presumption might
often lie in the other direction (Why would it be able to happen?)
Version 2: If Congress has specific distributional goals
that it pursues coherently and consistently, then in a sense it really won’t
care what the regulators do. Or more precisely, even if it doesn’t directly
rein them in, it will simply adjust its distributional bottom line so that
distribution comes out in aggregate the same as if the regulators had pursued
efficiency alone.
I think hardened law and economics types may be prone to
finding this line of reasoning more persuasive than it actually is, because
they are used to thinking about consistent rational choice by an individual
with coherent preferences. But in politics you get all the issues of collective
choice, along with pervasive agency costs that include political actors’
frequently greater interest in such things as personal credit-claiming, blame
avoidance, and symbolic gesturing, than in substantive outcomes. Thus, even
insofar as individuals fulfill the rational actor model of optimization under coherent
and consistently followed preferences, collective choice institutions in a
modern mass society should not be expected to do this.
Once again, while obviously one has to think about the
possibility that Congress will undo (or directly rein in) distributionally
minded agencies that are not adhering to pure efficiency (as well as those that
ARE adhering to pure efficiency), there is really no reason here for a general
presumption that it just won’t matter. That, rather, is the question to be
asked.
Here is a model I prefer to the “political Coase theorem”
for thinking about why, say, the left or the right might pursue particular
distributional (or other) fights as zealously as they sometimes do. Each time
you win a battle, you’re that one battle ahead, and it won’t necessarily be
offset elsewhere even if outcomes aren’t entirely independent and uncorrelated.
Suppose a baseball team figures to win about half of its
games. Bottom of the ninth with two outs, they’re down by one run but have the
tying and winning runs in scoring position. So if the batter gets a hit they
win, if he makes an out they lose.
Either way, they’re still a .500 team over the long run. But they’re one game ahead if he gets a game-winning hit, relative to the case where he makes the third out. And there’s no particular reason to think that this will be automatically offset. A win today doesn’t, at least inherently, make a loss tomorrow more likely than it would otherwise have been.
Either way, they’re still a .500 team over the long run. But they’re one game ahead if he gets a game-winning hit, relative to the case where he makes the third out. And there’s no particular reason to think that this will be automatically offset. A win today doesn’t, at least inherently, make a loss tomorrow more likely than it would otherwise have been.
Tax policy colloquium week 7: Zach Liscow paper, part 1
Yesterday at the colloquium, Zach Liscow presented his paper
“Democratic Law and Economics.” Before getting directly to the paper, I think it’s
useful to put it in a broader context that will be familiar to some
readers but perhaps not others.
The law and economics movement in law schools, which got
going in earnest about 40 years ago, in its early stages made a lot of strides
using an approach that some call “Econ 101ism.” As per Noah Smith:
“We all know
basically what 101ism says. Markets are efficient. Firms are competitive.
Partial-equilibrium supply and demand describes most things. Demand curves
slope down and supply curves slope up. Only one curve shifts at a time. No
curve is particularly inelastic or elastic; all are somewhere in the middle
(straight lines with slopes of 1 and -1 on a blackboard). Etc.”
Econ 101ism was a step forward for legal scholarship, but
not a step far enough. One had to understand what the logic of a standard
neoclassical analysis implied, but the next step required recognizing that its
assumptions might not always hold, and then asking what that would imply. It’s
a great orienting tool, but its seductive power to purport to answer so many
questions, from so parsimonious a starting point, can over-excite the
incautious if they forget that they need to take that next step of testing the
accuracy and sufficiency of its assumptions.
A more recent trend in what one might call tax or public
finance law and economics involves using a very simple model that purports to
answer lots of questions. The Atkinson-Stiglitz theorem holds (within the
specified terms of its model): “Where the utility function is separable between
labor and all commodities, no indirect taxes need be employed.”
Take the Mirrlees model, in which we want to base the tax on
ability but can only measure earnings, so we impose a labor income tax that is equivalent
to a uniform commodity tax. (Wages are used to buy commodities, and in a
one-period model one spends it all currently.) Atkinson-Stiglitz asks whether
one might get a better outcome by having non-uniform commodity taxes, e.g.,
taxing luxuries at a higher rate than the rest. It shows that, within its
terms, the answer to this question is NO unless some commodities are leisure
substitutes or complements. E.g., if I work more, I may substitute restaurant
meals for buying groceries (leisure substitute). Or if I work less I might want
to buy a telescope so I can spend hours stargazing (leisure complement). But
absent any of that, the uniform commodity tax is best.
Suppose one thought that taxing yachts at a higher rate
would have an admitted efficiency cost (discouraging yacht choice vs. other
consumption), but also an efficiency gain (raising revenue that permits one to
lower the labor income tax rate). So isn’t there a tradeoff, with even an
implication that there might be a net efficiency gain, since multiple smaller
distortions are often better than just one large one?
Answer: No. You still have to work to get the $$ to buy a
yacht, and working is just a way of getting to buy things. So one is still,
roughly speaking, discouraging labor supply as much as before, plus one is now
also distorting commodity choice. Hence there is now “double distortion”
without mitigation of the prior distortion.
Leading figures in tax or public finance law and economics
(e.g., Kaplow and Shavell) have shown how broad Atkinson-Stiglitz’s
implications might be. For example, one can think of an income tax as imposing higher
commodity taxes on future consumption than current consumption, creating double
distortion (discouragement of saving) without any mitigation of a consumption
tax’s admitted discouragement of work and market consumption. Hence, case
closed for the income tax? Yes unless there is more to the analysis, but the
point (as with Econ 101ism) is that there might be. (And for what it’s worth,
neither Atkinson nor Stiglitz agrees that based on their theorem one should
prefer consumption taxation to income taxation.)
Likewise, case closed (within the analysis) with regard to
using “legal rules” instead of the “tax system” to redistribute. Here the “tax
system” means, not Title 26 of the Internal Revenue Code, but a labor income
tax plus demogrant. “Legal rules” means pretty much anything else. E.g.,
income-conditioned speeding tickets, like they have in Finland. Product
liability or tort rules that favor consumers or accident victims on the ground
that they’re generally poorer. Mandatory contract clauses to protect tenants.
Inducing corporate managers to optimize for “stakeholders,” not just
shareholders, under a progressive redistributive rationale.
Under the view, using any of those types of vehicles to
address distributional concerns about rich vs. poor merely yields double
distortion. You’re still discouraging labor supply, insofar as becoming rich
subjects you to expected unfavorable treatment under those rules. Plus, you’re
departing from the efficient choice in those areas, which makes things worse
overall than if one had just used the labor income tax to address
distributional concerns.
The takeaway from this analysis was and is: All analysis of
“legal rules” and government policies outside the labor income tax should be
driven PURELY by considerations of efficiency. Leave redistribution purely to
the “tax system.”
This view has been highly influential in legal scholarship,
and also perhaps in regulatory policy as actually done. But it has inspired
pushback, both on theoretical grounds (based on whether the underlying
assumptions are sufficiently accurate and complete) and in light of concerns
that, in practice, it leads to too little progressivity if policymakers adopt
it in the realm of “legal rules,” but not when designing the tax system.
This, anyway, is vital background for discussing Liscow’s
“Democratic Law and Economics,” to which I will turn directly in my next
blogpost.
-->
Wednesday, October 09, 2019
NYU Tax Policy Colloquium, week 6: Katherine Pratt's "The Curious State of Tax Deductions for Fertility Treatment Costs"
As we
reached the 42.9 percent point (6 weeks out of 14 now in the books), it was
nice to have an abrupt topic shift - one of the things I like best about the
colloquium - in this case, from international tax the prior two weeks, to
Katherine Pratt's The
Curious State of Tax Deductions for Fertility Costs.
Narrowly speaking, this paper responds to a
phenomenon we will surely be growing increasingly familiar with in coming
years: a pompous, confused, biased, ignorant, and gratingly self-satisfied
opinion by a Trump judge, although this individual may have higher than average
judicial qualifications among the lot. The opinion at issue is Morrissey v.
United States, in which an Eleventh Circuit judge purported to offer a
"primer on the science of human reproduction," sharing with lucky
readers such insights as: "It is a biological fact that, unlike some lower
organisms ... human beings reproduce sexually .... Critically here, within the
human reproductive process, the male and female bodies have different roles and
purposes."
The judge's motive for so generously sharing
these insights with us is that "the circumstances of the case - and the
parties' competing contentions" made it seem necessary to him. More
specifically, he viewed the plaintiff's contention that an unmarried gay man
could claim medical deductions for assisted reproductive technology (ART)
expenses (such as for egg donation and fertilized egg surrogacy) as contrary to
nature, at least when backed up by (of course) statutory "plain
meaning."
Needless to say, the plain meaning is not so
clear as our judge-lecturer thinks. Under Code section 213(d)(1), medical
expenses include "amounts paid .. for the purpose of affecting any
structure or function of the body." I would think it clearly affects a
"function of the body" for the taxpayer's sperm to be successfully
inseminated in a fertile egg that may may eventually grow into a child who is
biologically his. Isn't it a "function" of the male body, in
producing sperm, to make possible one's having biological children? That end
result is certainly the evolutionarily selected function served by the male
production of sperm (if we want to talk Nature).
This is not to say that "plain
meaning" resolves the case in the taxpayer's favor. Rather, it shows that
other interpretive methods are needed. For example, the fact that the taxpayer
would not have needed to incur ART expenses in order to have a biological
child, had he been heterosexual and with a fertile female partner - a point of
central importance to the judge - clearly is relevant to the analysis. But now
we are engaged in a more complex statutory interpretation exercise than he
seems to realize is necessary, and one as to which his tediously
trying-to-seem-bemused lectures about Nature are unilluminating. The judge's
evident belief that section 213 shouldn't be available when people don't seek
to produce children in what he thinks is the natural way - and, admittedly,
thereby incur costs that could have been avoided had they used his preferred
method - involves statutory interpretation via purposive analysis. That's fair
enough, methodologically speaking, but it isn't "plain meaning."
Anyway, one reason Pratt wrote the article, in
the aftermath of Morrissey, is that the 11th Circuit opinion
carelessly (to put the best face on it) misstates actual IRS practice, insofar
as one can glean it from limited evidence, with respect to different types of
ART-related expenses incurred by differently situated taxpayers. So a bit of
clean-up crew was needed in this area, on which she's been writing for a while,
in addition to her wanting to address a set of very interesting issues around
the tax and other treatment of ART expenses. With that said, let's turn to a
few of those issues.
1) Infertility and dysfertility - Even after Morrissey, there are strong
grounds supporting the conclusion that section 213 medical deductions are
allowable for certain ART expenses, at least in the following scenario.
Say that a heterosexual married couple establishes that one of them is
infertile, and they therefore pay $$ for fertility treatments of the infertile
party. That appears to be deductible. There is also an IRS letter ruling (admittedly,
not constituting precedent) allowing various expenses incurred in connection
with egg donation to be deducted under section 213 by a woman who was unable to
conceive a child using her own eggs.
Morrissey does
not contradict allowing ART deductions with respect to the taxpayer's own
infertility (or that of "his spouse," as section 213 puts it). But
the taxpayer's argument, which the court rejected, would add dysfertility to
infertility as grounds for ART deductibility. As per Pratt's paper,
dysfertility "refers to individuals who cannot bear children because
they are single or in a same sex relationship."
Let's switch from statutory interpretation to policy - since, whether Morrissey is right or wrong as to the former, rejecting it as to the latter would call for legal change. I would argue that there is a compelling case for mandatory government-provided insurance coverage for ART for dysfertility, as well as infertility.
This obviously starts from mid-conversation, so far as government-provided health insurance coverage is concerned. I state it as generally as that to extend the sphere past income tax deductions for medical expenses to the realm of Medicare, Medicaid, single-payer, the mandated scope of universal health insurance coverage, etcetera.
I'd put the starting point for the argument as follows. From behind the veil regarding one's own particular identity within our society, one should recognize that it's very common to have a very strong desire for a biological child, or as close to it as possible, as a joint project with one's partner . One should further recognize that, again from behind the veil, one doesn't know whether one will be one of the people for whom this turns out to be relatively easy - i.e., a fertile heterosexual individual with a fertile heterosexual partner. From this perspective, both infertility and dysfertility are risks - partly converted by modern technology into financial risks, insofar as one can pay a lot of money for workarounds that did not always exist - against which it is rational to want to insure.
But why mandatory government insurance? This requires a market failure that the government can address better than private insurance firms. The most obviously relevant one here is adverse selection - widely recognized now as a key reason for favoring government provision in the healthcare arena, whether it be via the current ramshackle U.S. methods, single payer, or something else. It's very plausible that the government's superior ability to address adverse selection with respect to dysfertility - the risk of which gets affected by knowing one's own sexual orientation and partner preferences - creates a strong enough case to support the intervention.
The other classic issue in government vs. private insurance analyses is moral hazard. Here there is a difference as well. From the perspective of a private insurer, moral hazard is at work if people use ART coverage to do things that they wouldn't have done if forced to bear the full freight financially. But for the government this is not so clear. To a benign government, it's not just financial "waste" if motivated prospective parents get to have children with a particular desired relationship to themselves. (Yes, the fate of children in need of adoption is also part of the larger policy picture, but it's not clear that shutting off other routes to raising a child is part of the optimal response to that.)
2) Beyond dysfertility? - What about ART expenses incurred, say, by heterosexual couples that are neither infertile nor dysfertile? An administrative advantage of not requiring infertility or dysfertility is that one need not demand an inquiry into either when people incurred ART expenses. But this admittedly would come at a fiscal cost that would raise issues of moral hazard, insofar as one thinks these expenses might have been incurred out of a preference for neither going through pregnancy (even when feasible) nor adopting. But I'd be inclined to say the expenses should be covered even without either infertility or dysfertility. Going through pregnancy is a pretty huge thing, with significant potential health costs, impact on one's career and long-term earnings, etc. But I am leaving aside here questions of whether we are uneasy (e.g., for Handmaid's Tale-type reasons) about the extent to which surrogacy becomes a go-to. These are certainly beyond the scope of my expertise.
3) Why run ART expenses through section 213? - As a long literature discusses, income tax deductions for medical expenses are a bizarre way to increase overall government health insurance coverage, relative to what it would be if one simply repealed the provision without changing anything else in the legal and policy landscape. Medical deductions come with an adjusted gross-income related deductible, followed by a marginal tax rate-related co-pay, without its being obvious why this form of government insurance is being interacted with the income tax's general provision of ability insurance / under-diversified human capital insurance.
Even taking the use of section 213 as given, I suppose one might want to treat ART and adoption expenses in the same bucket, although to really do this right one might also want to throw in the marginal healthcare expenses that result from being pregnant, if these could be separately identified. And conceivably one would treat things in this bucket differently than other stuff, just as a well-designed health insurance schemes might vary the deductible, the co-pay, the cap if any on covered outlays, etc., based on the characteristics of particular areas.
4) The paper's proposed solution - Rather than discussing statutory changes that might directly address ART expenses, the paper proposes modifying section 213 in more general terms, so that it focuses on "inherently medical services" and on allowing taxpayers to "restore or approximate typical human functioning." This raises further interesting issues, although I won't explore them here, regarding, for example, the technology-driven rise of "inherently medical" procedures that might allow people to go way above the median (a la the use of human growth hormone by someone of average height who wants to become 6'5").
If only Descartes had met him
Sylvester, who nearly died this summer of a thymoma (along with a nearly disastrous general anesthesia episode that left him blind for 2 days) is now, many weeks post-surgery feeling well enough to meow plaintively, endlessly, and if I dare say so a tad annoyingly for food, to be followed by more food (perhaps more than his stomach will accept in so short a period).
He's so expressive of his often churning inner states that I'm sure Descartes would have realized how wrong he was to think animals are unfeeling automata, if only he had met the little fellow.
He's so expressive of his often churning inner states that I'm sure Descartes would have realized how wrong he was to think animals are unfeeling automata, if only he had met the little fellow.
Thursday, October 03, 2019
This week's Tax Policy Colloquium paper (by me)
This week at the NYU Tax Policy Colloquium, the paper we discussed
was mine - i.e., my work-in-progress, entitled Digital Service Taxes and the
Broader Shift From Determining the Source of Income to Taxing Location-Specific
Rents.
In recent decades, a number of fantastically successful, mainly American, multinational entities (MNEs) have risen to global economic hyper-prominence. While their market capitalizations and profits are high, reflecting that they earn substantial rents or quasi-rents, their aggregate global taxes are generally quite low, reflecting their ability to create stateless income.
It was a very fruitful session,
that has inspired my making a few expansions and clarifications of the analysis
in the version that I have posted.
Alas, I'm a bit handcuffed with
regard to including a lot of content here. I'm not going to re-post the link to
it, although you can readily find it on SSRN, as I'd rather have people read
the revised version than the currently posted one. But I'm not quite ready to
post that, since (1) I have some readers' comments that I want to look at
closely first, and (2) I'll be presenting it at U
Toronto Law School's tax policy workshop in a couple of weeks, and
might as well take advantage of that feedback as well.
I generally don't discuss the
colloquium sessions here, lest they lose their off-the-record status, with
potential inhibiting effects on discussion. And discussing it here as if it
were someone else's paper doesn't seem quite the thing to do either.
So why don't I settle for
posting the abstract, which at present goes something like this:
In recent decades, a number of fantastically successful, mainly American, multinational entities (MNEs) have risen to global economic hyper-prominence. While their market capitalizations and profits are high, reflecting that they earn substantial rents or quasi-rents, their aggregate global taxes are generally quite low, reflecting their ability to create stateless income.
Often, these MNEs are technology companies – but not always.
Starbucks, for example, enjoys high global profits and low taxes despite its
following a classic brick-and-mortar retail business model. This reflects that,
like its more obviously high-tech peers, it relies on valuable intellectual
property that helps it in creating both global pretax profitability and
stateless income.
Such MNEs’ rise has placed substantial pressure on existing
corporate income tax models. While the existing models might perhaps be
significantly improved, this would still leave market countries (where the
MNEs’ consumers are located) well short of being able to tax, as fully as they
might like, the location-specific rents that these companies earn by
interacting with their residents.
Market countries that use novel tax instruments, such as properly
designed digital services taxes (DSTs) to expand their capacity to reach such
location-specific rents, are not acting unreasonably, as judged within existing
(and fairly lax) norms for constraining and channeling countries’
self-interested behavior. DSTs also have the potential (although whether it
will be realized is uncertain) to improve, rather than worsen, global
efficiency and distribution. Whether they prove permanent or merely
transitional, DSTs look like harbingers of a new era in which entity-level
corporate taxation rightly focuses more on immobile factors and locational
rents, and less on decades-old doctrinal and semantic debates concerning the
supposedly “true” source of economic income and value creation.
Talk at Reed College last week on my forthcoming literature & inequality book
As noted previously, last week, while in Portland, I gave a talk at Reed College concerning my forthcoming book, currently called Dangerous Grandiosity: Literary Perspectives on High-End Inequality Through the First Gilded Age.
I have now posted a PDF version of my slides for the talk, which you can find here.
The book is expected out in April 2020, with Anthem Press. Its title may change, however, as I gather that common practice counsels having the lead portion of the title (i.e., before the semicolon) give greater notice than it currently does of what the book actually is, and is about.
I am making final textual changes now, after having gotten anonymous reviewer letters. While ( think it's fair to say that the reviewers were highly favorable, they did some editing changes. Worse still (as I like to put it), they made GOOD suggestions, suggesting that I mainly ought to follow them and indeed will.
I'm certainly available for talks regarding the book, especially in 2020.
I have now posted a PDF version of my slides for the talk, which you can find here.
The book is expected out in April 2020, with Anthem Press. Its title may change, however, as I gather that common practice counsels having the lead portion of the title (i.e., before the semicolon) give greater notice than it currently does of what the book actually is, and is about.
I am making final textual changes now, after having gotten anonymous reviewer letters. While ( think it's fair to say that the reviewers were highly favorable, they did some editing changes. Worse still (as I like to put it), they made GOOD suggestions, suggesting that I mainly ought to follow them and indeed will.
I'm certainly available for talks regarding the book, especially in 2020.